The categories that defined the immediate context of Fanon’s
last years and publications—decolonisation, nationalism, redemptive
violence—belong primarily to an historical era that ended, in the 1970s,
with the last victorious wars of national liberation. The central
notion at work in these categories, however, is both much older than
this historical sequence and no doubt much ‘younger’ than its
still-limited set of political consequences. Although its opponents had
already sought to consign this notion to the dustbin of conceptual
history well before Fanon himself came to rework it, its real significance is still oriented towards the future.
What is this familiar notion that has become
almost unrecognisable in our ultra-capitalist age, an age marked by
absolute commodification and ‘humanitarian’ imperialism? It is the
notion of autonomous political will. More precisely, it is the theory
and practice of an emancipatory ‘will of the people’ conceived in terms
that enable it to be both decisive and inclusive.
This is the notion that Rousseau and the
Jacobins put at the divisive centre of modern politics. It is the
practice that, after Hegel and Marx, Lenin confirmed as the central
element of modern revolutionary experience.[2] It is the practice that Fanon’s
own revolutionary contemporaries (Mao, Castro, Che Guevara, Giap,
Mandela...) preserved as their guiding frame of reference. It is also
the notion that has been most thoroughly forgotten if not repressed, in
both theory and practice, by the discipline that in recent decades has
largely appropriated Fanon’s legacy: the discipline of postcolonial studies. A preliminary requirement of any new ‘return to Fanon’
worthy of the name must involve the forgetting of this forgetting, in
order to remember a much older confrontation between the mobilisation of
popular political will and the myriad forces that seek to pacify and
‘devoluntarise’ the people.
This confrontation between active volition and imposed resignation stages the central drama of Fanon’s
work, early and late. Connecting his early existentialist account of
individual freedom with his later emphasis on patriotic duty and
commitment, ‘volonté [will]’ is the term
that links his psychological and his political work. Mobilisation of the
will of the people is the guiding priority of what we might call his
‘political psychology’. It integrates his strategic defence of ‘terror’
with his affirmation of a fully and concretely ‘universal humanism’. It
connects his French republican inheritance and his anti-colonial
internationalism. Mobilised and united, the indomitable will of the
people explains the triumph of the Algerian revolution and anticipates
its pan-African expansion; demobilised and dispersed, it yields in the
face of neo-colonial reaction. The same alternatives continue to define
the terms of anti-imperialist struggle to this day, from Haiti to
Palestine. Fanon should be read, in short, as one of the most insightful and uncompromising political voluntarists of the twentieth century.[3]
A glance through the formulations that recur in the texts that Fanon
wrote on behalf of the Algerian National Liberation Front (FLN) in the
1950s lends this characterisation some initial plausibility. Collected
in the posthumous volume Toward the African Revolution,
these articles are peppered with dozens of references to the ‘will of
the people’ and the ‘national will of the oppressed peoples’, their
‘will to independence’, their ‘will to break with exploitation and
contempt’, and so on.[4]
First and foremost the Algerian revolution ‘testifies to the people’s
will’, and the resulting situation is defined above all in terms of ‘the
armed encounter of the national will of the Algerian people and of the
will to colonialist oppression of the French governments’ (AR, 64, 130).
Any consideration of revolutionary Algeria, Fanon
insists, must recognise ‘the will of twelve million men; that is the
only reality’ (AR, 74). And as this will to independence advances
towards realisation of its purpose, so then affirmation of ‘a national
will opposed to foreign domination’ has become and will remain the
‘common ideology’ of the African liberation movement as a whole (AR,
153).
Fanon’s voluntarism is hardly less emphatic in the approach to psychology he begins to develop in his first book, Black Skin White Masks (1952). If as Fanon
(twice) observes ‘the tragedy of the man is that he was once a child’,
if the beginning of every life is always ‘drowned in contingency’, so
then it is through the deliberate and laborious ‘effort to recapture the
self and to scrutinize the self, it is through the lasting tension of
their freedom, that men will be able to create the ideal conditions of
existence for a human world’ (BS, 180-181). There are no ‘objective’
factors—no ethnic or cultural inheritance, no racial essence, no
historical mission—that should determine the course of such scrutiny and
creation. Since in ‘the world through which I travel I am endlessly
creating myself’, so then my only duty is to avoid ‘renouncing my
freedom through my choices [...]. I do not have the right to allow
myself to be mired in what the past has determined. I am not the slave
of the Slavery that dehumanized my ancestors’ (BS, 179). Solidarity with
others is a matter of freely assumed commitment, rather than an
automatic orientation inherited by a community. If then ‘the question of
practical solidarity with a given past ever arose for me, it did so
only to the extent to which I was committed to myself and to my
neighbour to fight for all my life and with all my strength so that
never again would a people on the earth be subjugated. It was not the
black world that laid down my course of conduct’ (BS, 177), but rather
my course of conduct that illuminates the scandalous devaluation of
‘blackened’ parts of the world. Fanon’s goal
here, after Sartre, is to ‘teach people to become aware of the
potentials they have forbidden themselves, of the passivity they have
paraded in just those situations in which what is needed is to hold
oneself, like a sliver, to the heart of the world, to interrupt if
necessary the rhythm of the world, to upset, if necessary, the chain of
command, but in any case, and most assuredly, to stand up to the world’
(BS, 57).
In the ancient philosophical struggle that pits will versus intellect as rivals for primary faculty of the mind, then, Fanon’s
allegiance is clear. The role of an engaged intellectual or artist,
first and foremost, is ‘to interpret the manifest will of the people’
(WE, 247). The effort to understand what is the case is secondary in
relation to a determination to prescribe (and then realise) what ought
to be the case. ‘In every age, among the people, truth is the property
of the national cause. No absolute verity, no discourse on the purity of
the soul, can shake this position. [...] Truth is that which hurries on
the break-up of the colonialist regime; it is that which promotes the
emergence of the nation’ in its freedom and autonomy (WE, 50).
I
Needless to say, like any consistent voluntarist, Fanon
is critical of distorted conceptions of will that turns it into one of
its several opposites—instinctive reflex, unthinking ‘fervour’, ‘blind’
impulse. Fanon condemns a ‘blind will toward
freedom’ (WE, 59; cf. BS, 2), for instance, precisely because he
recognises the minimal requirements of a consequential voluntarism.
These requirements are easily derived from the concept itself (and most
were anticipated by the first philosopher to grapple in detail with the
problem of a popular or ‘general’ will, Rousseau).
A consistent voluntarism requires, first, that political will indeed be considered as a matter of volition or will,
rather than compulsion, coercion or ‘instinct’. Voluntary action is a
matter of free deliberation and prescription. Political will is thought
through: it subsumes a ‘spontaneous’ enthusiasm or rebellion in an
organised mobilisation or a disciplined campaign. It affirms the primacy
of a conscious decision and commitment, independent of any ‘deeper’
(i.e. unconscious) determination, be it instinctual, historical, or
technological.
Second, a fully or universally emancipatory account of political will—i.e. a ‘humanist’ account in Fanon’s sense of the word—just as obviously requires that this be the will of the people
as such, and not of a group (defined by class, function, ethnicity...)
whose privileges or interests set them apart from the people.
Third, will is not just opposed to reflex or
impulse: it is equally opposed to mere imagination or wish. Political
will persists to the degree that it is able to realise or ‘actualise’
its prescription, to impose itself, i.e. to overcome the resistance of
those opposed to that prescription. Will is a matter of victory or
defeat. Victory requires the assembly and unity of the people, and on
that basis mobilisation of a force capable of vanquishing the enemies of
the people. Like any kind of will, political will is a matter of
determination and struggle, one that either continues and prevails or
else slackens and fails. The work of ‘total liberation’ that Fanon
anticipates ‘is bound to be hard and waged with iron determination
[...]. The colonial peoples must redouble their vigilance and their
vigour. A new humanism can be achieved only at this price’ (AR, 126).
Under the pressure of anti-colonial war, Fanon
rediscovers the strategic principle that guided Robespierre, Lenin and
Mao as they waged their own wars to end war: a truly inclusive or
universal ‘humanism’ will be achieved only through resolute struggle
with its adversaries, and not through an extension of existing forms of
tolerance, ‘recognition’ or ‘respect’, not through more appropriate or
sensitive forms of representation, acknowledgement, concern, management,
and so on.[5]
The rest of this essay will work through Fanon’s
approach to these general requirements of political will, starting with
the last: as his every reader knows, a version of this third
requirement was forced on Fanon the moment he became aware of the colour of his skin.
II
There are two general ways of
extinguishing the will of a people. The most reliable and secure method
is to lull them into a deferential passivity, such that the possibility
of a voluntary insurgency never arises. Under suitable conditions, this
sort of ‘hegemonic’ approach may only require manipulation of those
ideological apparatuses—education, the media, consumption,
entertainment...—required to guarantee the ‘manufacture of consent’. The
alternative is more direct and more abrasive, and involves the use of
whatever force is required to disperse, divide or pacify a group of
people; the ‘primitive accumulation’ of imperial power, no less than
what Marx called the primitive accumulation of capital, has almost
invariably involved reliance on such force. The colonialism that Fanon
devoted his life to dismantling combines both strategies. ‘The
colonised have this in common, that their right to constitute a people
is challenged’ (AR, 145), through a combination of coercion and
deference.
Conquest alone allows colonialism to begin.[6]
Colonialism can only continue, however, through colonisation of the
mind and the consolidation of a far-reaching ‘inferiority complex’.
Colonialism ‘holds a people in its grip’ by controlling its future and
by distorting and destroying its past, and by ‘emptying the native’s
brain of all form and content’ (WE, 210). Once established in its
position of military superiority, the colonial culture produces, through
a whole range of media, an unending ‘series of propositions that slowly
and subtly—with the help of books, newspapers, schools and their texts,
advertisements, films, radio—work their way into one’s mind and shape
one’s view of the world of the group to which one belongs’ (BS, 118).
Successful colonisation leads the oppressed to identify with the world
view of the oppressor. Since the colonial cultural machine leads one to
believe that ‘one is a Negro to the degree to which one is wicked,
sloppy, malicious, instinctual’, so then, encouraged on all sides to
identify with what is white, I come to ‘distrust what is black in me,
that is, the whole of my being’. ‘Voluntary’ internalisation of this
distrust completes the colonial project, and re-establishes a form of
slavery on a more robust footing. ‘The black Antillean is the slave of
this cultural imposition. After having been the slave of the white man,
he enslaves himself’.[7]
Colonialism thus takes hold of a territory to
the degree that it encourages ‘passivity’ and ‘despair’, if not
‘resignation’ or ‘fatalism’ among its indigenous inhabitants (DC, 82,
84). ‘A belief in fatality removes all blame from the oppressor; the
cause of misfortunes and of poverty is attributed to God’, and the
oppressed person is led to accept ‘the disintegration ordained by God’
and ‘bows down before the settler and his lot’ (WE, 54-55). In this way,
‘French colonialism has settled in the very centre of the Algerian
individual’ and systematically pursued a programme of ‘expulsion of
self, of rationally pursued mutilation’ (DC, 50). Carried to its
successful completion, colonial mind-control removes even the fantasy of
emancipation. ‘The settler’s work is to make even dreams of liberty
impossible for the native’ (WE, 93). Even to desire an end to
colonialism, in this context, would involve the libidinal equivalent of
‘suicide’.[8]
As doctor Fanon
diagnoses it, in other words, colonialism is first and foremost an
immense project to break the will of the colonised people. It is no
accident that the dominant theme of colonial characterisations of the
colonised is an insistence on their apparent lack of volition and
self-control. Colonial racism is first and foremost a systematic effort
to represent the indigenous people as ‘the unconscious and irretrievable
instrument of blind forces’. The ‘native’ is a being of pure instinct,
of dangerous reflexes and depraved impulses (WE, 41; cf. 250). ‘In
Europe the Negro has one function: that of symbolizing the lower
emotions, the baser inclinations, the dark side of the soul’ (BS, 147).
Within Algeria itself the stakes are higher, for obvious reasons, and
the ‘native’ impulse that comes to the fore is less an unbridled sexual
appetite than a murderous aggression. The native Algerian kills
‘savagely’ and ‘for no reason [...]. We find him incapable of
self-discipline, or of canalizing his impulses. Yes, the Algerian is a
congenital impulsive’, and his ‘impulsiveness is largely aggressive and
generally homicidal’ (WE, 296-298). As described by colonial
psychiatrists, Algerian natives are characterised by a more or less
complete absence of volition and reflection—by their ‘credulity’ and
‘persistent obstinacy’, a ‘mental puerility’ that is ‘always impulsive
and aggressive’, etc. (WE, 300). Unsurprisingly, colonial doctors even
managed to find a physiological basis for the north African’s ‘almost
animal impulsivity’ (WE, 303). The Algiers-based professor Porot, quoted
by Fanon in the closing pages of Wretched of the Earth,
pursues this logic to its conclusion when he describes, in 1935, the
‘native of north Africa’ as a ‘primitive creature whose life [is]
essentially vegetative and instinctive’ and who, deprived of a
distinctively human cerebral cortex, is dominated, like the inferior
vertebrates, by the diencephalon’ (WE, 301). As the World Health
Organisation’s Dr. A. Carothers would conclude twenty years later, the
most economical way of describing these impulse-governed Africans is as
‘lobotomised Europeans’ (WE, 302).
Confronted with the native or Negro,
colonialism sees a merely ‘natural’ rather than a social or civilised
being, and concludes ‘you can’t get away from nature’ (DC, 26). The
political response to such a characterisation is predictable, and little
different from the response recommend by classical (i.e. racist)
European liberalism, from Locke through Burke to Tocqueville and Mill.[9] ‘It was a sub-prefect who has now become a prefect who voiced the conclusion to me’, Fanon
remembers. ‘We must counter these natural creatures’, he said, ‘who
obey the laws of their nature blindly, with a strict, relentless ruling
class. We must tame nature, not convince it’. Discipline, training,
mastering, and today pacifying are the words most frequently used by the
colonialists in occupied territories’ (WE, 303).
But for all its literally ‘inhuman’
brutality, colonial oppression in its classical (i.e. racist) form is
undermined by a fundamental weakness which favours the eventual
empowerment of the oppressed. Its brutality is, again literally, obvious,
flagrant; it is rooted more in coercion than in deference, and it is
thus easier to judge and condemn. As Foucault would point out in the
decade following Fanon’s death, the successful exercise of power is ‘proportional to its ability to hide its own mechanisms’.[10] Whereas in non-colonised capitalist societies the hegemonic cultural and educational system, Fanon
observes, ‘the structure of moral reflexes handed down from father to
son’, compounded by innumerable ‘expressions of respect for the
established order, serve to create around the exploited person an
atmosphere of submission and of inhibition which lightens the task of
policing considerably. In the capitalist countries a multitude of moral
teachers, counsellors and ‘bewilderers’ separate the exploited from
those in power’. But in ‘the colonial countries, on the contrary, the
policeman and the soldier, by their immediate presence and their
frequent and direct action maintain contact with the native and advise
him by means of rifle butts and napalm not to budge. It is obvious
here that the agents of government speak the language of pure force’
(WE, 38, my emphasis). The full clarity that Marx assumed would
accompany the development of capitalism—the assumption that as
capitalism replaces feudal ‘exploitation veiled by religious and
political illusions’ with ‘naked, shameless, direct, brutal
exploitation’, so then ‘man is at last compelled to face with sober
senses his real conditions of life’[11]—has so far only prevailed in the countries colonised by capital.
Colonial and racist forms of oppression
thereby lend themselves to conscious and thus deliberate or ‘voluntary’
resistance. ‘Since the racial drama is played out in the open, the black
man has no time to “make it unconscious.” [...] The Negro’s inferiority
or superiority complex or his feeling of equality is conscious. These
feelings forever chill him. They make his drama’, in the absence of any
conventional neurotic deviation or ‘amnesia’ (BS, 116). The only
appropriate response to such feelings is engagement in direct
confrontation and struggle, rather than any attempt at refutation,
re-interpretation, or re-representation. Colonial diagnoses of the
‘native personality’, the nature of ‘Muslim society’ or the plight of
the ‘Algerian woman’, etc., merit one and only one ‘valid challenge’:
‘the experience of revolution’ (DC, 51). The fact that such struggle may
or may not (yet) succeed, given the current balance of forces, is a
secondary issue: faced with the fact of colonialism, ‘our historic
mission is to sanction all revolts, all desperate actions, all those
abortive attempts drowned in rivers of blood’ (WE, 207).
Fanon understood
this well before the Algerian revolution began. Prior to his commitment
to that revolution, however, he hadn’t yet found an adequate vehicle for
this anti-colonial consciousness, one that might allow the colonised to
become (to quote Marx again) the ‘authors and actors of their own
drama’.[12] In keeping with one of the fundamental characteristics of political will itself, for Fanon,
the will of the people would only become a collective and political (as
opposed to a merely psychological) reality through its direct
mobilisation in Algeria’s national liberation struggle. Fanon’s
‘populism’ has nothing to do with any form of ethnic or cultural
communitarianism, let alone any form of jingoistic chauvinism. ‘The most
solid bastion of the Algerian Revolution’, Fanon
will learn, is not a material interest or a socio-ethnic identity, but
rather the ‘spiritual community’ of a people ‘realizing its unity’
through combat and determination (DC, 101).
The will of the people only becomes the basis
of an revolutionary or emancipatory political practice to the degree
that the one term informs the other: the ‘people’ become a political
category insofar as they come to share a will to independence, and such a
will is emancipatory insofar as it embraces the whole of an oppressed
people. The only genuine emancipation is deliberate or voluntary
self-emancipation. Fanon knows as well as Marx that ‘it is the oppressed peoples who must liberate themselves’.[13]
(By the same token, he knows that people whose liberation is thrust
upon them—like the inhabitants of Martinique and Guadeloupe in
1848—remain fundamentally unfree[14]).
Decolonisation is precisely this, the conversion of an involuntary
passivity into a self-mastering activity. Decolonisation ‘transforms
spectators crushed with their inessentiality into privileged actors,
with the grandiose glare of history’s floodlights upon them [...].
Decolonization is the veritable creation of new men. But this creation
owes nothing of its legitimacy to any supernatural power; the “thing”
which has been colonized becomes man during the same process by which it
frees itself’ (WE, 36-37).
III
Committed to their revolution, Fanon
has confidence in the people. The people are adequate to the task of
self-emancipation. This is both an ‘article of faith’, the
presupposition of a revolutionary commitment, and a lesson learned from
militant experience. On the one hand, Fanon is confident that ‘everything can be explained to the people, on the single condition that you really want them to understand’.[15]
Understanding fosters autonomy. ‘The more the people understand, the
more watchful they become, and the more they come to realize that
finally everything depends on them and their salvation lies in their own
cohesion, in the true understanding of their interests, and in knowing
who their enemies are’ (WE, 191). On the other hand, under the
extraordinary pressure of events, ‘in Algeria we have realized that the
masses are equal to the problems which confront them’ (WE, 193). No less
than Rousseau, Fanon is confident that if the
people are free to deliberate and settle on their own course of action,
then sooner or later they will solve the problems they face (or in
Rousseau’s more emphatic terms, if the circumstances allow for a
universal or general will, if a group is indeed able to sustain a single
and undivided will, then such willing will never err[16]). Determination of the popular will may take time, but in the end it is the only reliable way of getting things right.
Algeria’s experience proves, Fanon
notes, ‘that the important thing is not that three hundred individuals
form a plan and decide upon carrying it out, but that the whole people
plan and decide even if it takes them twice or three times as long.
[...] People must know where they are going, and why’. Of course, it
takes time to determine a course of action, and ‘the future remains a
closed book so long as the consciousness of the people remains
imperfect, elementary, and cloudy’. The legacy of colonial
‘discouragement’, compounded by under-developed means of communication
and isolation from the rest of the work, mean that ‘awakening of the
whole people will not come about all at once’ (WE, 193-194tm).[17] Nevertheless, this awakening is for Fanon both a fact and a norm: the Algerian people are awakening, and they can
be trusted to decide on the course of their own trajectory. As he
explains in one of the most striking passages of his book, such
self-determination applies as much to post-colonial construction as it
does to anti-colonial struggle:
In the same way that during the period
of armed struggle each fighter held the fortune of the nation in his
hand, so during the period of national construction each citizen ought
to continue in his real, everyday activity to associate himself with the
whole of the nation, to incarnate the continuous dialectical truth of
the nation and to will the triumph of man in his completeness here and
now. If the building of a bridge does not enrich the awareness of those
who work on it, then that bridge ought not to be built and the citizens
can go on swimming across the river or going by boat. The bridge should
not be ‘parachuted down’ from above; it should not be imposed by a deus ex machina upon
the social scene; on the contrary it should come from the muscles and
the brains of the citizens [...]. In this way, and in this way only,
everything is possible (WE, 200-201).
For Fanon, then—and
this is where he is most distant from Lenin or Mao—the people rather
than their leaders or party is the only adequate subject of—political
will. A party has its role to play, but
the party should be the direct
expression of the masses. The party is not an administration responsible
for transmitting government orders; it is the energetic spokesman and
the incorruptible defender of the masses. In order to arrive at this
conception of the party, we must above all rid ourselves of the very
Western, very bourgeois and therefore contemptuous attitude that the
masses are incapable of governing themselves. In fact, experience proves
that the masses understand perfectly the most complicated problems (WE,
188).[18]
For Lenin it is the party that
guides the industrial proletariat who in turn guide the working classes
and labouring people as a whole. The Leninist party provides the
theoretical framework through which the people will ‘spontaneously’
recognise and learn the lessons of their own experience.[19] Carried by his commitment to the Algerian revolution, Fanon
effectively inverts the order of priority. ‘While in many colonial
countries it is the independence acquired by a party that progressively
informs the infused national consciousness of the people, in Algeria it
is the national consciousness, the collective sufferings and terrors
that make it inevitable that the people must take its destiny into its
own hands’ (DC, 16).
Nevertheless, Fanon
remains very close to Lenin (and then Mao) in his insistence that on
the primacy of determination itself as the decisive element of politics:
what matters is the popular will,
precisely, rather than popular opinions, habits or culture. For Lenin,
early and late, the priority is always ‘achieving unanimity of will
among the vanguard of the proletariat as the fundamental condition for
the success of the dictatorship of the proletariat’, itself the
condition of genuine popular empowerment and democracy.[20]
Given the actual balance of class forces, ‘victory over the bourgeoisie
is impossible without a long, stubborn and desperate life-and-death
struggle which calls for tenacity, discipline, and a single and
inflexible will’.[21]
For Mao, likewise, political initiative belongs to those whose
‘unshaken conviction’ and ‘unceasing perseverance’ enables them (to
adapt one of Mao’s metaphors) to ‘move mountains’.[22]
The goal is, first, to unify, concentrate and intensify the people’s
‘will to fight’ against their oppressors, and then to establish a form
of government that will most ‘fully express the will of all the
revolutionary people’, if not ‘the unanimous will of the nation’.[23]
In keeping with Rousseau’s fundamental distinction between the general will of the people and the mere ‘will of all’[24],
what matters is a collective capacity to identify and will the general
interest as such, rather than the aggregate interest or opinion of all
individuals as individuals. Lenin privileges the party because (as he
sees it) it is the subject most capable of willing and acting with the
sort of clarity, unity and ‘iron determination’ that political struggle
requires; the proletariat, further, is that class whose economic
circumstances and conditions of work (their coordination as employees of
a large scale enterprise, their lack of any privately owned means of
production) confront them with the truth of capitalist exploitation in
its most unadulterated form, while freeing them from the ‘vacillation’
characteristic of small landowners and the petty bourgeoisie. The
proletariat is in a position to see clearly what they are up against, in
conditions that foster solidarity, discipline and resolve while
discouraging compromise and reform; suitably led, they are positioned,
in short, to act as the vanguard for labouring people as a whole.
Inverting Lenin’s distribution of roles, Fanon
privileges the peasantry for much the same reasons: in the colonial
situation, the peasantry is that sector of the wider population most
capable of sustaining a revolutionary will. In Fanon’s
Algeria rather like Mao’s Hunan, it is the peasantry who are best
placed to ‘smash all the trammels that bind them and rush forward along
the road to liberation’.[25]
In the colonies it is the urban working class that tends to vacillate
under the pressure of anti-colonial struggle. Modern towns emerge here
like ‘little islands of the mother country’ (WE, 121), and ‘in the
colonial territories the proletariat is the nucleus of the colonized
population which has been most pampered by the colonial regime’ (WE,
108).[26]
The peasant farmers, by contrast, are the first to confront the full
reality of colonial oppression, and the first to draw the unavoidable
consequences. ‘The starving peasant, outside the class system, is the
first among the exploited to discover that only violence pays. For him
there is no compromise, no possible coming to terms; colonization and
decolonization are simply a question of relative strength’ (WE, 61). Fanon
knows, of course, that in industrialized colonial countries the
peasantry may be ‘the least aware, the worst organized, and at the same
time the most anarchical element’. In such places, the peasant’s
‘individualism, lack of discipline, liking for money’, and so on, may
lead them to play an ‘objectively reactionary’ role (WE, 111). In
colonial Algeria, by contract, grounded in respect for their ‘living’
traditions, the peasants are the most ‘disciplined element’, they are
the most ‘virtuous’ members of the people in more or less exactly
Rousseau’s sense of the term. ‘In their spontaneous movements the
country people as a whole remain disciplined and altruistic. The
individual stands aside in favour of the community’ (WE, 112), whose
members stand ‘ready to sacrifice themselves completely’ (WE, 127).[27]
The revolution will thus find its first and
most reliable partisans in the countryside. ‘The country districts
represent inexhaustible reserves of popular energy’ (WE, 128), and here
‘the peasantry precisely constitutes the only spontaneously
revolutionary force of the country’ (WE, 123). When isolated urban
revolutionaries and intellectuals finally turn their attention to the
rural areas they ‘discover that the mass of the country people have
never ceased to think of the problem of their liberation except in terms
of violence, in terms of taking back the land from the foreigners, in
terms of national struggle, and of armed insurrection. It is all very
simple’ (WE, 127). By the same token, when the revolution spreads from
the countryside to the towns, it initially takes hold in those districts
populated by destitute refugees from the countryside. ‘The rebellion,
which began in the country districts, will filter into the towns through
that fraction of the peasant population which is blocked on the outer
fringe of the urban centres, that fraction which has not yet succeeded
in finding a bone to gnaw in the colonial system [...]. It is within
this mass of humanity, this people of the shanty towns, at the core of the lumpenproletariat, that the rebellion will find its urban spearhead’. Like their rural cousins, the déclassé
shackdwellers know that struggle offers the only way out, and ‘by
militant and decisive action they will discover the path that leads to
nationhood. They won’t become reformed characters to please colonial
society, fitting in with the morality of its rulers; quite on the
contrary, they take for granted the impossibility of their entering the
city save by hand grenades and revolvers’ (WE, 129-130).
Fanon’s confidence
in the people, then, is not unconditional: he is confident in the people
insofar as they actively will and determine the course of their own
political destiny. In the case of an oppressed or colonised people, this
means that affirmation of the category of the people is inseparable
from direct participation in their will to self-emancipation. If the
measure of successful decolonisation is given by the fact that ‘a whole
social structure is being changed from the bottom up’, the
‘extraordinary importance of this change is that it is willed, called
for, demanded’ (WE, 35-36). No other kind of change has any chance of
success. Fanon knows as well as Lenin that you
cannot ‘turn society upside down [...] if you have not decided from the
very beginning [...] to overcome all the obstacles that you will come
across in so doing’ (WE, 37).
In Algeria, of course, determination of the
will of the people took on the particular form required by the obstacle
it faced. Everything turns, here, on the moment ‘when a decisive
confrontation brought the will to national independence of the people
and the dominant power face to face’ (DC, 74). In Algeria and other
European settler colonies, victory in this confrontation depended and
foremost on a willingness to overcome the main basis of this
power—ruthless and systematic political violence—on its own terms. Given
what he’s up against, ‘the colonized man finds his freedom in and
through violence’ (WE, 86). Educated by the experience of fruitless
decades of negotiated ‘reforms’, ‘it is the intuition of the colonized
masses that their liberation must, and can only, be achieved by force’
(WE, 73). The Algerian revolutionaries are obliged to resort to terror
for same reason as the Jacobins in 1793 or the Bolsheviks in 1918: by
1956, ‘the revolutionary leadership found that if it wanted to prevent
the people from being gripped by terror it had no choice but to adopt
forms of terror which until then it had rejected’.[28]
Since ‘colonialism is not a thinking machine nor a body endowed with
reasoning faculties’, since ‘it is violence in its natural state’, so
then the partisans of the national liberation struggles came to the
conclusion that ‘it will only yield when confronted with greater
violence’ (WE, 61).[29]
IV
Fanon and
his contemporaries came to this conclusion at a time when colonial
violence was both far more brutal than anti-colonial violence (as
epitomised in the gruesome massacres carried out at Sétif, Moramanga,
Sharpeville, and so on [WE, 72; cf. 89]) and far from invincible (as
indicated by the victories won in the 1950s by ‘people’s war’ in
Vietnam, Cuba, and Algeria itself). Fanon
reached his conclusions at a time when he was still confident that
‘there is no colonial power today which is capable of adopting the only
form of contest which has a chance of succeeding, namely, the prolonged
establishment of large forces of occupation’ (WE, 74). It would be a
mistake to generalise Fanon’s specific
strategic emphasis here. Several familiar components of his account of
the national liberation struggle apply more broadly, however, to an
account of voluntarist political practice in general.
First of all, of course, political will is practiced through struggle
against an enemy, a difficulty or an injustice. By definition, there is
no will in the absence of constraint or resistance. Like it or not, Fanon
discovers, I find myself thrown into a world structured in dominance
and oppression, ‘in which I am summoned into battle; a world in which it
is always a question of annihilation or triumph’ (BS, 178). A decision
to participate in the struggle against colonial oppression already marks
a critical stage in the process that ‘expels the fear, the trembling,
the inferiority complex, from the flesh of the colonised’ (AR, 151).[30] Commitment to the struggle allows Fanon
to conform to a basic Leninist prescription—wherever possible, ‘to go
on the offensive’ (AR, 179tm). Willingness to fight the ‘superior’ or
‘master race’ is already an immediate assertion of equality that
evacuates the older value system. In combat, ‘the native discovers that
his life, his breath, his beating heart are the same as those of the
settler. He finds out that the settler’s skin is not of any more value
than a native’s skin; and it must be said that this discovery shakes the
world in a very necessary manner. All the new, revolutionary assurance
of the native stems from it. For if, in fact, my life is worth as much
as the settler’s, his glance no longer shrivels me up nor freezes me,
and his voice no longer turns me into stone’ (WE, 45). For those engaged
in armed struggle the only pertinent imperative, as Sartre puts it, is
‘to thrust out colonialism by every means in
their power’ (Sartre, Preface, WE, 21). Once it begins, the priority is
simply to ‘intensify the armed struggle’ until justice prevails. ‘All
attempts at diversion by the adversary must be quelled’ (AR, 162).
Confronted by a colonial power, ‘we must cut off all her avenues of
escape, asphyxiate her without pity, kill in her every attempt at
domination’ (AR, 130). In such a situation, appeals to ‘peaceful
negotiation’ and ‘international mediation’ are only so many attempts to
confuse the issue.
More importantly, participation in struggle unites its participants and thus constitutes them as a
people. The goal of anti-colonial struggle is not reformation or
improvement of colonial situation but its elimination through ‘the
grandiose effort of a people, which had been mummified, to rediscover
its own genius, to reassume its history and assert its sovereignty’ (AR,
83-84). Victory in such a struggle ‘not only consecrates the triumph of
the people’s rights; it also gives to that people consistency,
coherence, and homogeneity’ (WE, 292). Previously, the colonized people
had been ‘reduced to a body of individuals who only find cohesion when
in the presence of the colonizing nation’ (WE, 292). Now, however, ‘all
the degrading and infantilising structures that habitually infest
relations between the colonised and the coloniser [have been] suddenly
liquidated’, and in place of the old ‘frenzied attempt at identification
with the coloniser, the Algerian has brought into existence a new,
positive, efficient personality, whose richness is provided [mainly...]
by his certainty that he embodies a decisive moment of the national
consciousness’ (AR, 102-103).
This capacity to assemble and to form
voluntary and cohesive associations is a central feature in any account
of political will, and a large part of the anti-colonial project
involves determination of ‘the precise points at which the peoples, the
men and the women, could meet, help one another, build in common’ (AR,
178). As a rule, ‘the masses should be able to meet together, discuss,
propose, and receive directions’—insofar as they help energise a general
will to deliberate and act, ‘the branch meeting and the committee
meeting are liturgical acts’ (WE, 195). Everything from the distribution
of radio sets across to the countryside to the development of suitably
patriotic forms of art and literature should contribute to ‘the
assembling of the people, a summoning together for a precise purpose.
Everything works together to awaken the native’s sensibility and to make
unreal and unacceptable the contemplative attitude, or the acceptance
of defeat’.[31]
‘The mobilization of the masses, when it arises out of the war of
liberation, introduces into each man’s consciousness the ideas of a
common cause, of a national destiny, and of a collective history’ (WE,
93). Forged in struggle, the new nation comes to enjoy a properly
‘monolithic’ degree of national unity (AR, 62).
National liberation is to be achieved by the people as a whole. Fanon
has no more sympathy than Lenin himself for merely ‘terroristic’ or
‘ultra-leftist’ undertaken by a neo-Blanquist clique, but he knows
better than Lenin that ‘an unceasing battle must be waged to prevent the
party from ever becoming a willing tool in the hands of a leader’ (WE,
184). Whatever is decided, ‘the success of the decision which is adopted
depends upon the coordinated, conscious effort of the whole of the
people’ (WE, 199): leaders and organisers exist to facilitate and
clarify the process of making a decision, but not to take it themselves.
‘No leader, however valuable he may be, can substitute himself for the
popular will’ (WE, 205). On the contrary, ‘to hold a responsible
position in an underdeveloped country is to know that in the end
everything depends on the education of the masses’. To educate the
masses politically, Fanon explains, is simply
‘to try, relentlessly and passionately, to teach the masses that
everything depends on them; that if we stagnate it is their
responsibility, and that if we go forward it is due to them too, that
there is no such thing as a demiurge, that there is no famous man who
will take the responsibility for everything, but that the demiurge is
the people themselves and the magic hands are finally only the hands of
the people’ (WE, 197).
Fanon demands a
similar commitment to direct participation on the part of that group
whose ‘spontaneous orientation’ appears to favour detachment:
intellectuals, artists, writers, who must all ‘understand that nothing
can replace the reasoned, irrevocable taking up of arms on the people’s
side’.[32]
A ‘national literature’ worthy of the name can only be ‘a literature of
combat, in the sense that it calls on the whole people to fight for
their existence as a nation’, and presents their ‘will to liberty
expressed in terms of time and space’ (WE, 240). In short, the popular
struggle is not to be ‘saluted as an act of heroism but as a continuous,
sustained action, constantly being reinforced’ (AR, 151). Although the
former may prepare the ground for the latter, the temporality of
political will is more fundamentally a matter of constancy and
accumulation than it is of transformative instants or leaps.
Collective participation in violent struggle,
however, certainly does involve crossing a point of no-return. In a
situation where ‘almost all the men who called on the people to join in
the national struggle were condemned to death or searched for by the
French police, confidence was proportional to the hopelessness of each
case. You could be sure of a new recruit when he could no longer go back
into the colonial system’ (WE, 85). As Saint-Just and Robespierre
learned in their own way, there is no more secure a basis for a
patriotic or ‘general will’ than participation in a struggle for
collective salvation in which the only possible outcome is victory or
death. ‘The practice of violence binds [the people] together as a whole,
since each individual forms a violent link in the great chain, a part
of the great organism of violence which has surged upward in reaction to
the settler’s violence in the beginning. The groups recognize each
other and the future nation is already indivisible. The armed struggle
mobilizes the people; that is to say, it throws them in one way and in
one direction’ (WE, 93). Thus thrown, the only ‘logical end of this will
to struggle is the total liberation of the national territory’ (AR,
43). For the guerrilla soldiers themselves, the solidarity born of an
irreversible commitment sustains brooks no compromise. ‘Henceforward,
the interests of one will be the interests of all, for in concrete fact everyone will be discovered by the troops, everyone will be massacred—or everyone will be saved. The motto “look out for yourself,” the atheist’s method of salvation, is in this context forbidden’ (WE, 47).
What is imperative, instead, is to rely on ourselves.
Since ‘a will cannot be represented’, as Rousseau explained, so then
‘sovereignty, being nothing more than the exercise of the general will,
can never be alienated [and...] can only be represented by itself; power
can indeed be transferred but not will’.[33] As far as the active willing
of the popular will is concerned, there is no substitute or
representative who might take the place of the people themselves—this is
a lesson that Lumumba learned to his cost, at the end of his own
life-and-death struggle, when he made the fatal mistake of making an
appeal to the United Nations (an institution that serves to ‘crush the
will to independence of people’) rather than to his own loyal partisans,
or to allies established through a genuine ‘friendship of combat’ (AR,
195-196).[34]
Such self-reliance points to another basic
feature of a voluntarist approach: its commitment to the here and now,
to decisive action in the present moment, and its consequent rejection
of terms that proceed through deferral, ‘reform’ or ‘development’. What
is at stake is a claim to that ‘independence which will allow the
Algerian people to take its destiny wholly in hand’ (AR, 101), all at
once, without waiting for recognition or approval from the colonial
master. The goal is not to reform the colonial situation but to abolish
it, not to improve a situation of partial dependence but to escape it.
The FLN does not seek to incorporate colonial ‘modernisation’ as a
difficult but necessary chapter in the development of the nation, but to
eliminate it: ‘instead of integrating colonialism, conceived as the
birth of a new world, in Algerian history, we have made of it an
unhappy, execrable accident’ (AR, 101). For the FLN, then, ‘bargaining
of any kind is unthinkable’ (AR, 62), and ‘this refusal of progressive
solutions, this contempt for the “stages” that break the revolutionary
torrent and cause the people to unlearn the unshakable will to take
everything into their hands at once in order that everything may change,
constitutes the fundamental characteristic of the struggle of the
Algerian people’.[35] In keeping with Fanon’s
neo-Jacobin logic, the will of the people, where one exists, not only
demands but incarnates an immediate and unconditional sovereignty.
In this respect at least, Fanon’s position might be better described as neo-Jacobin than as neo-Bolshevik: for Fanon,
compared with Lenin, the exercise of political will is more fully
independent of an ‘objective’ historical development, of the so-called
laws or stages of economic development. Yes, says Fanon,
‘decolonisation is proceeding, but it is rigorously false to pretend
and to believe that this decolonisation is the fruit of an objective
dialectic which more or less rapidly assumes the appearance of an
absolutely inevitable mechanism’. Revolutionary optimism here is not a
response to an objective assessment of the situation: rather, ‘optimism
in Africa is the direct product of the revolutionary action of the
African masses’ (AR, 170-171), pure and simple. Ultimately, there is
nothing ‘beneath’ the will of the people that might guide its course.
There are no historical or economic laws to which it must conform. Fanon
offers no excuse or alibi: ‘sooner or later a people gets the
government it deserves’ (WE, 198). Everything depends on us, and on ‘the
firmness of our commitment’ (AR, 172).
This means, furthermore, that the
self-determination of the will is itself a sufficient guide to action
and the consequences of action. Considered in isolation and on its own
terms, to will involves a ‘total’ and ‘sincere’ commitment to one’s
experience, without reserve, without second-guessing, without reflection
upon unconscious or ulterior motives, mitigating circumstances, etc.
This is the real reason for Fanon’s famous objection, in Black Skin, to Sartre’s interpretation of negritude as a merely transitional moment in a dialectic that subsumes it. Fanon
is no less convinced than Sartre himself, of course, of the essential
freedom and autonomy of consciousness. But in his critique of negritude
as a form of consciousness determined by its
place in a logic of development, Sartre forgets that ‘a consciousness
committed to experience is ignorant, has to be ignorant, of the essences
and the determinations of its being’, at least if the latter are to be
understood as providing a rationale for that experience which is
supposedly ‘deeper’ than its own conscious self-determination.[36]
On either the individual or the collective level, such ‘wilful
ignorance’ is indeed an irreducible aspect of the practical primacy of
the will. On either level, ‘nothing is more unwelcome than the
commonplace: “You’ll change, my boy; I was like that too when I was
young... you’ll see, it will all pass.” The dialectic that brings
necessity into the foundation of my freedom drives me out of myself’
(BS, 103), just as submission to the logic of historical or economic
‘development’ drives the newly liberated nation back into the coils of
necessity. Rather than submit to what is feasible, to what circumstances
permit, the first duty of revolutionary activists is to commit to their
vision and their will to achieve it—in Fanon’s
case, ‘to turn the absurd and the impossible inside out and hurl a
continent against the last ramparts of colonial power’ (AR, 181).
It’s no accident, finally, that Fanon’s
work should be concerned with both the individual and collective
dimensions of political will. Willing (as voluntarists from Rousseau to
Marx to Lenin appreciate) is an individual activity, but political
will only begins with an individual’s voluntary commitment to and
participation in a collective project. Confirming Marx’s point about the
need to ‘educate the educators’ (i.e. to recognise the full
‘coincidence of the changing of circumstances and of human activity or
self-changing’)[37], Fanon
observes that ‘the thesis that men change at the same time that they
change the world has never been so manifest as it now is in Algeria’
(DC, 18). One the one hand, Fanon writes in
1961, ‘during the last few years I have had occasion to verify a very
classic fundamental idea: that honour, dignity, and respect for the
given word can only manifest themselves in the framework of national and
international homogeneity. From the moment that you and your like are
liquidated like so many dogs, you have no other resource but to use all
and every means to regain your importance as a man’ (WE, 295). On the
other hand, there can be no waiting for the ‘political process’ to
transform the individuals needed to sustain it. Each individual needs to
remember that ‘it is necessary at all times and in all places to make
explicit, to de-mystify, and to harry the insult to mankind that exists
in oneself. There must be no waiting until the nation has produced new
men; there must be no waiting until men are imperceptibly transformed by
revolutionary processes in perpetual renewal’ (WE, 304-305).
As Rousseau might say, civic vertu is not first a public concern and only later
a private one; virtue is precisely the free and deliberate alignment of
the private with the public, of the individual with the patrie.
From the beginning, the project of national liberation involves an
existential choice. ‘Every Algerian faced with the new system of values
introduced by the Revolution is compelled to define himself, to take a
position, to choose’. Participation in the revolution thus triggers a
literal renaissance: a new ‘person is born, assumes his autonomy, and
becomes the creator of his own values’.[38]
In this sense, ‘the liberation of the individual does not follow
national liberation. An authentic national liberation exists only to the
precise degree to which the individual has irreversibly begun his own
liberation’.[39]
If ‘independence produces the spiritual and material conditions for the
reconversion of man’, at the same time the people’s ‘inner mutation’
enables ‘the emergence of the Nation and the growth of its sovereignty’
(DC, 159).
V
In keeping with this voluntarist logic, the central sections of Wretched of the Earth
are best read, I think, as an outline of the basic steps involved in
the constitution of a general or political will, i.e. the assertion and
assumption of a disciplined collective project. ‘An underdeveloped
people must prove, by its fighting power, its ability to set itself up
as a nation, and by the purity of every one of its acts, that it is,
even to the smallest detail, the most lucid, the most self-controlled
people’ (DC, 12).
The constitution of a general will begins
with an initial moment of voluntary association and commitment, the
‘spontaneous’ assertion of national solidarity. Such an explosion of
emancipatory revolt is marked by elation and enthusiasm. ‘Every native
who takes up arms is a part of the nation which from henceforward will
spring to life [...]. They hold one doctrine only: to act in such a way
that the nation may exist. There is no program; there are no speeches or
resolutions, and no political trends. The problem is clear: the
foreigners must go; so let us form a common front against the oppressor
and let us strengthen our hands by armed combat’ (WE, 131). This moment
of irreversible commitment is essential, and what follows is in a sense
only a matter of discovering how best to sustain it. At this stage,
‘each man or woman brings the nation to life by his or her action, and
is pledged to ensure its triumph in their locality’ (132). This is the
occasion for a ‘cleansing’ purity and ‘collective ecstasy’. ‘In
undertaking this onward march, the people legislates, finds itself, and
wills itself to sovereignty. In every corner that is thus awakened from
colonial slumber, life is lived at an impossibly high temperature. There
is a permanent outpouring in all the villages of spectacular
generosity, of disarming kindness, and willingness, which cannot ever be
doubted, to die for the “cause.” All this is evocative of a
confraternity, a church, and a mystical body of belief at one and the
same time. No native can remain unmoved by this new rhythm which leads
the nation on’ (WE, 132-133). Spontaneous solidarity and commitment,
however, has its limits both in time and space. At this stage
‘initiative is localized’, restricted in time and space: ‘the program of
each locally constituted group is local liberation. If the-nation is
everywhere, then she is here. One step further, and only here is she to
be found. Tactics are mistaken for strategy’ (WE, 132).[40]
A second stage is required to convert local
and immediate liberation to national and lasting independence. This is
the moment of organisation and discipline—the moment, forever associated
with Lenin’s legacy, of ‘iron determination’. Initially caught off
guard, the enemy regroups. Machine guns and napalm force the popular
mobilisation to change its tactics. The ‘spontaneous impetuosity which
is determined to settle the fate of the colonial system immediately is
condemned, in so far as it is a doctrine of instantaneity, to
self-repudiation. For the most everyday, practical realism takes the
place of yesterday’s effusion, and substitutes itself for the illusion
of eternity’. (WE, 134). If it’s to prevail, the struggle must convert a
‘peasant revolt’ into a ‘revolutionary war’. A ‘central authority must
be created’ and the national forces assembled and coordinated. ‘The
leaders of the rebellion come to see that even very large-scale peasant
risings need to be controlled and directed into certain channels’. (WE,
135).
It is especially important to preserve the
unity of the people and the national will to independence in the face of
the next turn in the colonial screw. Confronted by a more united and
more organised adversary, the colonial or neo-colonial power reverts to
the old strategy of divide and rule: it makes minor concessions here,
hands out political favours there, while cracking down on ‘isolated
extremists’ (WE, 138-140).[41]
Those waging the struggle ‘must not waver.
They must not imagine that the end is already won [...]. Once again,
things must be explained to them; the people must see where they are
going, and how they are to get there’, and ‘this taking stock of the
situation, this enlightening of consciousness, and this advance in the
knowledge of the history of societies are only possible within the
framework of an organization, and inside the structure of a people’ (WE,
141, 143).
If they are sufficiently organised and
disciplined, the people will subsequently manage to cope with the
inevitable betrayals that accompany victory over the immediate enemy. If
‘nationalism, that magnificent song that made the people rise against
their oppressors, stops short, falters, and dies away on the day that
independence is proclaimed’ (WE, 203), then (for reasons that
Machiavelli and then Rousseau anticipated) an independent people will
need to find ways of renewing its spirit. On this point, Fanon’s
last book testifies to some ambivalence. On the one hand, he reiterates
his confidence in popular autonomy. ‘When the people have taken violent
part in the national liberation they will allow no one to set
themselves up as “liberators.” They show themselves to be jealous of the
results of their action and take good care not to place their future,
their destiny, or the fate of their country in the hands of a living
god. Yesterday they were completely irresponsible; today they mean to
understand everything and make all decisions. Illuminated by violence,
the consciousness of the people rebels against any pacification’ (WE,
94-95). On the other hand, however, memory of the national liberation
struggle does not itself preclude the treachery of the post-colonial
bourgeoisie. For Fanon no less than Rousseau
or Robespierre, a popular or general will faces only one genuinely
lethal threat: the private interests of the rich and privileged. As Fanon conceives things, the postcolonial bourgeois is faced with a choice between two forms of betrayal:
The historical vocation of an authentic
national middle class in an underdeveloped country is to repudiate its
own nature in so far it as it is bourgeois, that is to say in so far as
it is the tool of capitalism, and to make itself the willing slave of
that revolutionary capital which is the people. In an underdeveloped
country an authentic national middle class ought to consider as its
bounden duty to betray the calling fate has marked out for it, and to
put itself to school with the people: in other words to put at the
people’s disposal the intellectual and technical capital that it has
snatched when going through the colonial universities. But unhappily we
shall see that very often the national middle class does not follow this
heroic, positive, fruitful, and just path; rather, it disappears with
its soul set at peace into the shocking ways—shocking because
anti-national—of a traditional bourgeoisie, of a bourgeoisie which is
stupidly, contemptibly, cynically bourgeois (WE, 150).[42]
Unhappily, more often than not the
postcolonial bourgeoisie betrays its nation rather than its class, and
‘just steps into the shoes of the former European settlement’ (WE, 152).
There it actively undermines the national project, and while covering
its tracks with pseudo-patriotic ritual, confirms the tribal,
occupational and regional privileges approved by their colonial
counterparts (158-159).[43]
As the ‘people stagnate deplorably in unbearable poverty, slowly they
awaken to the unutterable treason of their leaders’ (WE, 167). Meanwhile
‘colonialism, which had been shaken to its very foundations by the
birth of African unity, recovers its balance and tries now to break that
will to unity by using all the movement’s weaknesses’, by exploiting
all ‘ethnic’ and ‘spiritual’ rivalries, real or imagined (WE, 160).
On the eve of anti-colonial victory in 1961, Fanon
rediscovers a lesson learned by Lenin in the wake an anti-capitalist
victory in 1917: in order to sustain a truly inclusive will of the
people, in order to establish the rule of genuine democracy, the people
must first smash its bourgeois simulacrum. In 1961, the peoples of
Africa face a similar choice as to that faced by the peoples of Russia
in 1917: their ‘national bourgeoisies, who are quite clear as to what
their objectives are, have decided to bar the way to that unity, to that
coordinated effort on the part of two hundred and fifty million men to
triumph over stupidity, hunger, and inhumanity at one and the same time.
This is why we must understand that African unity can only be achieved
through the upward thrust of the people, and under the leadership of the
people, that is to say, in defiance of the interests of the
bourgeoisie’ (WE, 164). The only solution is a return to Lenin’s point
of departure: ‘the combined effort of the masses led by a party and of
intellectuals who are highly conscious and armed with revolutionary
principles ought to bar the way to this useless and harmful middle
class’ (175), and thereby guarantee, by all means necessary,
‘restoration of the country to the sacred hands of the people’ (166).
Again, ‘we must repeat, it is absolutely necessary to oppose vigorously
and definitively the birth of a national bourgeoisie and a privileged
caste’ (WE, 200). In the end, a struggle which ‘mobilizes all classes of
the people and which expresses their aims and their impatience, which
is not afraid to count almost exclusively on the people’s support, will
of necessity triumph’ (WE, 246).
As anyone can see, fifty years after Fanon’s
death, a struggle which fears or fails to count on such support is sure
to lose out to the neo-colonial forces that continue to shape our
world.[44] Fanon’s
account of political will is limited, no doubt, by the particular
circumstances under which it was devised. To some extent, at least,
these circumstances encouraged Fanon to qualify (rather than exaggerate) the voluntarist orientation of his approach. Under the pressure of a ‘manichean’ struggle, Fanon
occasionally yielded to the temptation of conceiving decolonisation in
terms of an abrupt replacement (a ‘total, complete, and absolute
substitution’ [WE, 35]) rather than a deliberate transformation. So long
as the oppressor can be conceived as an overt ‘stranger in our midst’,
so then it might seem that his mere ‘removal’ or ‘abolition’ will
eliminate oppression itself (WE, 40-41). Again like Lenin, Fanon’s
insistence on the ‘invincible’ will power of the people risks
converting affirmation of this power into its opposite—a quasi-automatic
reflex, precisely, the guarantee of an ‘inevitable’ or ‘definite’
victory.[45] So long as Fanon
conceives of oppression in simplified or ‘undifferentiated’ terms,
grounded on the model of foreign military conquest (AR, 81), so then the
solution he proposes will suffer from symmetrical limitations. Fanon’s
strategic emphasis on armed struggle, in particular, risks the
reduction of action to reaction, the determination of a solution by the
nature of the problem it aims to solve. If during the liberation war
this solution helps foster ‘the holy and colossal energy that keeps a
whole people at the boiling point’ (DC, 17), it is poorly equipped to
limit the eventual evaporation of such energy.
Of course, Fanon
was the first to understand that ‘in an initial phase, it is the action,
the plans of the occupier that determine the centres of resistance
around which a people’s will to survive becomes organised’ (DC, 32). We
have since entered a different phase. Fanon
was wrong to believe that, as a general rule, ‘between oppressors and
oppressed everything can be solved by force’ (WE, 72), but he was right
and remains right to remind us that imperial and neo-imperial relations
are founded in violence. He was and remains right to insist that, in the
end, only the determined and united will of the people offers any means
of overcoming such violence. If we’ve learned anything in the fifty
years since Fanon’s death, however, we’ve
learned that the will to transform these relations needn’t be bound by
an obligation to fight on their terms, or by their means. Confronted
with the legacy and persistence of colonial domination and capitalist
exploitation, the fundamental political question remains: are there, or
are there not, ‘enough people on this earth resolved to impose reason on
this unreason’ (DC, 18)?
Abbreviations:
BS: Black Skin, White Masks [1952], trans. Charles Lam Markmann [1967], London, Pluto, 2008.
DC: A Dying Colonialism [1959], trans. Haakon Chevalier, Pelican Books 1970. [Translation of L’An cinq de la révolution algérienne, 1959].
WE: Wretched of the Earth [1961], trans. Constance Farrington, New York, Grove, 1968.
AR: Toward the African Revolution [1964], trans. Haakon Chevalier, New York, Grove Press, 1967.
[1]. A slightly earlier and substantially shorter version of this essay first appeared in Nigel Gibson (ed.), Living Fanon: Global Perspectives, London, Palgrave Macmillan, 2011.
[2]. Reference to these thinkers here is justified on the basis of analogy and pertinence, rather than direct influence.
[3]. The most pointed critique of Fanon’s voluntarism, written from the perspective of the people’s war in Vietnam, remains Nguyen Nghe, ‘Frantz Fanon et les problèmes de l’indépendance’, La Pensée, no. 107, February 1963, pp. 23-36; cf. Neil Lazarus, Resistance in Postcolonial African Fiction, New Haven, Yale University Press, 1990, pp. 8-17. More sympathetic recent readings of this aspect of Fanon’s work include Nigel Gibson’s Fanon: The Postcolonial Imagination, London, Wiley-Blackwell, 2003, pp. 181, 202 and passim, and Ato Sekyi-Otu’s Fanon’s Dialectic of Experience, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996, p. 171.
[4].
AR, 159, 113 and passim. By the same token, the only ‘hope of French
colonialism is to shatter the national will’ (AR, 74), and ‘colonialism
resorts to every means to break the people’s will [...]. French
colonialism since 1954 has wanted nothing other than to break the will
of the people, to destroy its resistance, to liquidate its hopes’ (DC,
98, 101).
[5]. As Richard Pithouse argues, ‘Black Skin, White Masks is a book about the futility of the politics of recognition’, in which Fanon
demonstrates that ‘reason walks out of the room when a black body walks
in’. Rather than continue to pursue an elusive recognition, Fanon’s account dramatises ‘the necessity of action’ (Pithouse, letter to the author, 7 October 2010).
[6].
The colonial relation to the Algerian woman, likewise, is not primarily
a matter of hegemonic manipulation; ‘straight off, with the maximum of
violence, there is possession, rape, near-murder’ (DC, 31).
[7].
BS, 148-189. Decolonisation, then, involves at the most elementary
level a project to ‘change people’s minds’. ‘The colonized peoples, the
peoples who have been robbed, must lose the habits of mind which have
characterized them up to now’ (WE, 143). They must gain the capacity
literally to ‘make up their own mind’. Human behaviour, as Fanon concluded in Black Skin White Masks,
is ‘not only reactional [...]. To educate man to be actional,
preserving in all his relations his respect for the basic values that
constitute a human world, is the prime task of him who, having taken
thought, prepares to act’ (BS, 173). ‘Initially subjective, the breaches
made in colonialism are the result of a victory of the colonised over
their old fear and over the atmosphere of despair distilled day after
day by a colonialism that has incrusted itself with the prospect of
enduring forever’ (DC, 38). ‘Old superstitions began to crumble.
Witchcraft, maraboutism [...], belief in the djinn, all things that
seemed to be part of the very being of the Algerian, were swept away by
the action and practice initiated by the Revolution’ (DC, 124).
[8].
‘The effect consciously sought by colonialism was to drive into the
natives’ heads the idea that if the settlers were to leave, they would
at once fall back into barbarism, degradation, and bestiality. On the
unconscious plane, colonialism therefore did not seek to be considered
by the native as a gentle, loving mother who protects her child from a
hostile environment, but rather as a mother who unceasingly restrains
her fundamentally perverse offspring from managing to commit suicide and
from giving free rein to its evil instincts’ (WE, 211).
[9]. Cf. Domenico Losurdo, Liberalism: A Counter-History, trans. Gregory Elliott, London, Verso, 2011.
[10]. Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality, Volume One: An Introduction, trans. Robert Hurley, New York, Pantheon, 1978, p. 86.
[11]. Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Communist Manifesto, Beijing, Foreign Languages Press, 1970, p. 35.
[12]. Marx, The Poverty of Philosophy [1847], Beijing, Foreign Languages Press, 1966, p. 109. Black Skin
anticipates the solution, but abstractly. Where a standard (Adlerian)
Eurocentric approach seeks to assign blame for an ethnic ‘inferiority
complex’ on its victims, Fanon’s response to
such a victim is perfectly clear: ‘I will tell him, “The environment,
society are responsible for your delusion.” Once that has been said, the
rest will follow of itself, and what that is we know. The end of the
world’ (BS, 168). Until the outbreak of Algeria’s war, however, Fanon lacked the concrete instrument that might accomplish this end. In 1952, Fanon—a
veteran of the French army—still considered himself to be ‘a Frenchman’
and not an ‘outsider’: ‘I am personally interested in the future of
France, in French values, in the French nation’ (BS, 157).
[13]. AR, 105. cf. Marx, ‘Rules and Administrative Regulations of the International Workingmen’s Association’ [1867], in Collected Works of Marx and Engels, London, Lawrence & Wishart, 1975-2005, pp. XX, 441.
[14].
In Martinique (unlike Haiti), ‘the Negro steeped in the inessentiality
of servitude was set free by his master’. He did not act, he was ‘acted
upon’. The ‘upheaval reached the Negroes from without’ and made no
fundamental difference: they ‘went from one way of life to another, but
not from one life to another [...]. The Negro knows nothing of the cost
of freedom, for he has not fought for it’ (WSBM, 171-172).
[15]. Fanon
understands the implications of the alternative position perfectly
well: ‘if you think that you don’t need the people, and that on the
contrary they may hinder the smooth running of the many limited
liability companies whose aim it is to make the people even poorer, then
the problem is quite clear. For if you think that you can manage a
country without letting the people interfere, if you think that the
people upset the game by their mere presence, whether they slow it down
or whether by their natural ignorance they sabotage it, then you must
have no hesitation: you must keep the people out’ (WE, 189).
[16]. Cf. Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Social Contract 1:7, 2:3.
[17]. Fanon’s
approach here is again best read as a variation on Lenin’s. Popular
‘consciousness slowly dawns upon truths that are only partial, limited,
and unstable. As we may surmise, all this is very difficult. The task of
bringing the people to maturity will be made easier by the thoroughness
of the organization and by the high intellectual level of its leaders.
The force of intellect increases and becomes more elaborate as the
struggle goes on, as the enemy increases his maneuvers and as victories
are gained and defeats suffered. The leaders show their power and
authority by criticizing mistakes, using every appraisal of past conduct
to bring the lesson home, and thus insure fresh conditions for
progress’ (WE, 146-147; cf. Lenin, ‘Can the Bolsheviks Retain State
Power?’, Selected Works, Moscow, Progress Publishers, 1968, one volume], 379.).
[18]. The political contribution of the legal and non-violent i.e. reformist parties, in Fanon’s Algeria as much as in Lenin’s Russia, is vitiated at the level of their fundamental volonté:
‘inside the nationalist parties, the will to break colonialism is
linked with another quite different will: that of coming to a friendly
agreement with it’ (WE, 124). ‘The national political parties never lay
stress upon the necessity of a trial of armed strength, for the good
reason that their objective is not the radical overthrowing of the
system. Pacifists and legalists, they are in fact partisans of order’
(WE, 59)—a new or ‘reformed’ order, no doubt, but certainly not the
‘disorder’ of revolution as such. As far as these reformists are
concerned, the question of an unqualified will to independence never
crosses the threshold of consciousness. For them, ‘every attempt to
break colonial oppression by force is a hopeless effort, an attempt at
suicide, because in the innermost recesses of their brains the settler’s
tanks and airplanes occupy a huge place. When they are told “Action
must be taken,” they see bombs raining down on them, armoured cars
coming at them on every path, machine-gunning and police action ... and
they sit quiet. They are beaten from the start. There is no need to
demonstrate their incapacity to triumph by violent methods; they take it
for granted in their everyday life and in their political maneuvers’
(WE, 63).
[19].
Cf. Vladimir Lenin, What is to be Done? [1902], Peking, Foreign
Languages Press, 1978, pp. 154-155; Lars T. Lih, Lenin Rediscovered :
What Is to Be Done? In Context, Leiden, Brill, 2006) Lih, ‘Lenin and the
Great Awakening’, in Sebastian Budgen et al. (eds.), Lenin Reloaded:
Towards a Politics of Truth, Durham NC, Duke University Press, 2007, pp.
284-287; Hal Draper, The ‘Dictatorship of the Proletariat’ from Marx to
Lenin, New York, Monthly Review Press, 1987. For Mao, likewise, ‘the
leading body of the Party [is] the concentrator of the will of the whole
Party’, which is in turn ‘the representative of the interests of the
masses and the concentrator of their will’ (Mao Tse-Tung, ‘Resolution on
Certain Questions in the History of our Party’ [1945], Selected Works,
Beijing, Foreign Languages Press, 1961-1977, 5 vols., vol. III, p.
209.).
[20]. Lenin, ‘Preliminary Draft Resolution of the Tenth Congress of the RCP on Party Unity’ [1921], Selected Works,
p. 626. Via dictatorship of the proletariat, Lenin argues, democracy
‘for the first time becomes democracy for the poor, democracy for the
people, and not democracy for the money-bags’, but precisely for this
reason ‘the dictatorship of the proletariat imposes a series of
restrictions on the freedom of the oppressors, the exploiters, the
capitalists. We must suppress them in order to free humanity from wage
slavery, their resistance must be crushed by force [...]. Democracy for
the vast majority of the people, and suppression by force, i.e.,
exclusion from democracy, of the exploiters and oppressors of the
people—this is the change democracy undergoes during the transition from
capitalism to communism’, Lenin, State and Revolution [1917], Selected Works, pp.324-325.
[22]. Mao, ‘The Foolish Old Man Who Removed the Mountains [1945], Selected Works III, 322.
[23]. Mao, ‘On New Democracy’ [1940], Selected Works II, 352; Mao, ‘On Coalition Government’, Selected Works, vol. III, p. 263.
[24]. Rousseau, Social Contract 2:3.
[25]. Mao, ‘Report on an Investigation of the Peasant Movement in Hunan’ [1927], Selected Works, vol. I, pp. 23-24.
[26].
‘In capitalist countries, the working class has nothing to lose; it is
they who in the long run have everything to gain. In the colonial
countries the working class has everything to lose; in reality it
represents that fraction of the colonized nation which is necessary and
irreplaceable if the colonial machine is to run smoothly: it includes
tram conductors, taxi drivers, miners, dockers, interpreters, nurses,
and so on’ (WE, 109).
[27].
By contrast, ‘the country people are suspicious of the townsman. The
latter dresses like a European; he speaks the European’s language, works
with him, sometimes even lives in the same district; so he is
considered by the peasants as a turncoat who has betrayed everything
that goes to make up the national heritage. The townspeople are
“traitors and knaves” who seem to get on well with the occupying powers,
and do their best to get on within the framework of the colonial
system. This is why you often hear the country people say of town dwellers that they have no morals’ (WE, 112).
[28]. DC, 40. ‘Not enough attention’, Fanon
notes, ‘has been given to the reasons that lead a revolutionary
movement to choose the weapon that is called terrorism’ (DC, 40). ‘The
naked truth of decolonization evokes for us the searing bullets and
bloodstained knives which emanate from it. For if the last shall be
first, this will only come to pass after a murderous and decisive
struggle between the two protagonists. That affirmed intention to place
the last at the head of things, and to make them climb at a pace (too
quickly, some say) the well-known steps which characterize an organized
society, can only triumph if we use all means to turn the scale,
including, of course, that of violence’ (WE, 37).
[29].
In a colonial context, ‘violence alone, violence committed by the
people, violence organized and educated by its leaders, makes it
possible for the masses to understand social truths and gives the key to
them. Without that struggle, without that knowledge of the practice of
action, there’s nothing but a fancy-dress parade and the blare of the
trumpets. There’s nothing save a minimum of readaptation, a few reforms
at the top, a flag waving: and down there at the bottom an undivided
mass, still living in the middle ages, endlessly marking time’ (WE,
147).
[30].
Once this step has been taken, whatever happens on the battlefield,
‘the inferiority complex, the fear and the despair of the past’ can no
longer be ‘reimplanted in the consciousness of the people’ (DC, 19).
[31].
WE, 243. After a period of initial resistance to a foreign technology,
over the course of the mid 1950s Algerians adopted the radio as a means
of collective deliberation and struggle. Broadcasts of ‘The Voice of
Fighting Algeria’ helped in the ‘consolidating and unifying the people’,
and ‘having a radio meant [...] buying the right of entry into the
struggle of an assembled people’ (DC, 68). This development illustrates
the voluntarist logic of Fanon’s cultural
nationalism more generally. ‘We believe that the conscious and organized
undertaking by a colonized people to re-establish the sovereignty of
that nation constitutes the most complete and obvious cultural
manifestation that exists’ (WE, 245), precisely because (active,
self-determining) culture is distinct from (passive, ‘objective’) custom
or folklore. ‘The living expression of the nation is the moving
consciousness of the whole of the people; it is the coherent,
enlightened action of men and women’ (WE, 204). ‘A national culture is
not a folklore, nor an abstract populism that believes it can discover
the people’s true nature [...]. A national culture is the whole body of
efforts made by a people in the sphere of thought to describe, justify,
and praise the action through which that people has created itself and
keeps itself in existence’ (WE, 233). By contrast, ‘the desire to attach
oneself to tradition or bring abandoned traditions to life again does
not only mean going against the current of history but also opposing
one’s own people’ (WE, 224).
[32]. WE, 226. It wouldn’t be hard, of course, to trace the neo-Bolshevik streak in Fanon’s
psycho-aesthetic preferences, from the admiration he expresses for
‘serenity’ with which young Vietnamese ‘fanatics’ face firing squads
(BS, 177) to his portrait of the ALN’s major Chawki, a man with an
almost ‘murderous hardness’ in his eyes, a man ‘difficult to deceive, to
get around’, who cannot be intimidated or distracted (AR, 181).
[33]. Rousseau, Social Contract 2.1; cf. 3:15.
[34].
‘In reality, the UN is the legal card used by the imperialist interests
when the card of brute force has failed’ or run its course (AR, 195).
[35]. AR, 103. A similar determination is characteristic of what Fanon
calls the ‘Third World’ state of mind: ‘the flagrant refusal to
compromise and the tough will that sets itself against getting tied up
are reminiscent of the behaviour of proud, poverty-stricken adolescents,
who are always ready to risk their necks in order to have the last
word. All this leaves Western observers dumbfounded’ (WE, 82).
[36].
Sartre, in other words, has failed to live up to his own insistence on
the autonomous transcendence of consciousness: if Sartre’s diagnosis of
negritude is correct, Fanon argues, then ‘it
is not I who make a meaning for myself, but it is the meaning that was
already there, pre-existing, waiting for me. It is not out of my bad
nigger’s misery, my bad nigger’s teeth, my bad nigger’s hunger that I
will shape a torch with which to burn down the world, but it is the
torch that was already there, waiting for that turn of history [...]
Jean-Paul Sartre, in this work, has destroyed black zeal’ (BS, 102-103; Fanon is referring to Sartre’s 1948 essay ‘Black Orpheus’).
[37]. Marx, ‘Theses on Feuerbach’, §3.
[38]. DC, 83. Already in Black Skin,
the psychoanalyst’s goal is ‘to help my patient to become conscious of
his unconscious’, to help ‘put him in a position to choose action (or
passivity) with respect to the real source of the conflict—that is,
toward the social structures’ (BS, 74-75).
[39]. AR, 103. Again, ‘when the nation stirs as a whole, the new man is not an a posteriori product
of that nation; rather, he co-exists with it and triumphs with it. This
dialectical requirement explains the reticence with which adaptations
of colonization and reforms of the facade are met. Independence is not a
word which can be used as an exorcism, but an indispensable condition
for the existence of men and women who are truly liberated, in other
words who are truly masters of all the material means which make
possible the radical transformation of society’ (WE, 310). The resulting
‘voluntarisation’ embraces even aspects of domestic e.g. conjugal life:
‘the Algerian couple rids itself of its traditional weaknesses at the
same time that the solidarity of the people becomes a part of history.
This couple is no longer an accident but something rediscovered, willed,
built’ (DC, 96).
[40].
Naïve enthusiasm creates new pitfalls. The inexperienced intellectual
who joins the popular struggle can be dazzled by people’s ‘good faith
and honesty’, and thereby become ‘opportunist’. ‘The danger that will
haunt him continually is that of becoming the uncritical mouthpiece of
the masses; he becomes a kind of yes-man who nods assent at every word
coming from the people, which he interprets as considered judgments, as
the literal incarnation of the truth (WE, 49).
[41].
As partisans of national independence in countries all over the world
would soon discover, in the face of a political movement that ‘was
beginning to “embody the national will” and to constitute a danger for
the colonial regime, parties which have their origin in ethnic or
regional differences spring up. It is the entire tribe which is turning
itself into a political party, closely advised by the colonialists. The
conference table can now be pulled out. The party which advocates unity
will be drowned in the computations of the various splinter groups,
while the tribal parties will oppose centralization and unity, and will
denounce the party of unity as a dictatorship’ (WE, 118-119).
[42].
‘Bereft of ideas, because it lives to itself and cuts itself off from
the people, undermined by its hereditary incapacity to think in terms of
all the problems of the nation as seen from the point of view of the
whole of that nation, the national middle class will have nothing better
to do than to take on the role of manager for Western enterprise, and
it will in practice set up its country as the brothel of Europe’ (WE,
154). Meanwhile, however, through their mobilisation, ‘the people come
to understand that wealth is not the fruit of labour but the result of
organized, protected robbery [...]. The land belongs to those that till
it. This is a principle which has through explanation become a
fundamental law of the Algerian revolution’ (WE, 191).
[43].
Such is the ‘Thermidorian’ moment in the anticolonial revolution: ‘all
the decentralizing tendencies spring up again and triumph, and the
nation falls to pieces, broken in bits’ (WE, 183).
[44]. There can be no arguing with Fanon
when he insists that, faced with the blackmail of neoliberal
‘modernisation’, ‘we should flatly refuse the situation to which the
Western countries wish to condemn us. Colonialism and imperialism have
not paid their score when they withdraw their flags and their police
forces from our territories. For centuries the capitalists have behaved
in the underdeveloped world like nothing more than war criminals.
Deportations, massacres, forced labour, and slavery have been the main
methods used by capitalism to increase its wealth, its gold or diamond
reserves, and to establish its power’. The formerly colonised peoples
need to remember what they are entitled to, what they are ‘due’—and the
colonising capitalist powers need to remember ‘that in fact they must pay’ (WE, 100-103).
[45]. See for instance DC, 19; AR, 169; WE, 84, 88.