Twelve
Theses on Changing the World without taking Power
John
Holloway, The
Commoner, 2002
I
- The starting point is negativity.
We
start from the scream, not from the word. Faced with the mutilation
of human lives by capitalism, a scream of sadness, a scream of
horror, a scream of anger, a scream of refusal: NO.
Thought,
to be true to the scream, must be negative. We do not want to
understand the world, but to negate it. The aim of theorising is to
conceptualise the world negatively, not as something separate from
practice, but as a moment of practice, as part of the struggle to
change the world, to make it a place fit for humans to live in.
But
how, after all that has happened, can we even begin to think of
changing the world?
- A world worthy of humanity cannot be created through the state.
For
most of the last century, efforts to create a world worthy of
humanity were
focussed
on the state and the winning of state power. The main controversies
(between ‘reformists’ and ‘revolutionaries’) were about how
to win state power, whether by parliamentary or by
extra-parliamentary means. The history of the twentieth century
suggests that the question of how to win state power was not very
important. In all cases, the winning of state power failed to bring
about the changes that the militants hoped for. Neither reformist nor
revolutionary governments succeeded in radically changing the world.
It
is easy to accuse all the leaderships of these movements of
‘betraying’ the
movements
which they led. So many betrayals suggest, however, that the failure
of
radical,
socialist or communist governments lies much deeper. The reason that
the state cannot be used to bring about radical change in society is
that the state itself is a form of social relations that is embedded
in the totality of capitalist social relations. The very existence of
the state as an instance separated from society means that, whatever
the contents of its policies, it takes part actively in the process
of separating people from control of their own lives. Capitalism is
simply that: the separating of people from their own doing. A
politics that is oriented towards the state inevitably reproduces
within itself the same process of separating: separating leaders from
led, serious political activity from frivolous personal activity. A
politics oriented towards the state, far from bringing about a
radical change in society, leads to the progressive subordination of
opposition to the logic of capitalism.
We
can see now that the idea that the world could be changed through the
state
was
an illusion. We are fortunate enough to be living the end of that
illusion.
3.
The only way in which radical change can be conceived today is not as
the taking
of
power but as the dissolution of power.
Revolution
is more urgent than ever. The horrors arising from the capitalist
organisation
of society are becoming more and more intense. If revolution through
the winning of state power has proved to be an illusion, this does
not mean that we should abandon the question of revolution. But we
must think of it in other terms: not as the taking of power, but as
the dissolution of power.
II
4.
The struggle for the dissolution of power is the struggle for the
emancipation of
power-to
(potentia) from power-over (potestas).
To
even think of changing society without taking power, we must make a
distinction
between power-to (potentia) and power-over (potestas).
Any
attempt to change society involves doing, activity. Doing, in turn,
implies
that
we have the capacity to do, the power-to-do. We often use ‘power’
in this sense, as something good, as when a united action with others
(a demonstration or even a good seminar) makes us feel ‘powerful’.
Power in this sense is rooted in doing: it is power-to-do.
Power-to-do
is always social, always part of a social flow of doing. Our ability
to
do
is produced by the doing of others and creates the conditions for the
future doing of others. It is impossible to imagine a doing that does
not integrate in some way with the doing of others, past, present or
future.
- Power-to is transformed into power-over when doing is broken.
The
transformation of power-to into power-over implies the breaking of
the social
flow
of doing. Those who exercise power-over separate the done from the
doing of others and declare it to be theirs. The appropriation of the
done is at the same time the appropriation of the means of doing, and
this allows the powerful to control the doing of the doers. The doers
(humans, understood as active) are thus separated from their done,
from the means of doing and from doing itself. As doers, they are
separated from themselves. This separation, which is the basis of any
society in which some exercise power over others, reaches its highest
point in capitalism.
The
social flow of doing is broken. Power-to is transformed into
power-over. Those who control the doing of others now appear as the
Doers of society, and those
whose
doing is controlled by others become invisible, without face, without
voice.
Power-to-do
no longer appears to be part of a social flow, but exists in the form
of an individual power. For most people the power-to-do things
becomes transformed into its opposite, powerlessness, or, at most,
the power-to-do things determined by others. For the powerful,
power-to-do becomes transformed into power-over, the power to tell
others what to do, and therefore a dependence upon the doing of
others.
In
present society, power-to exists in the form of its own negation, as
power-over.
Power-to
exists in the mode of being denied. This does not mean that it ceases
to exist. It exists, but it exists as denied, in antagonistic tension
to its own form of existence as power-over.
6.
The breaking of doing is the breaking of every aspect of society,
every aspect of
ourselves.
The
separation of the done from the doing and from the doers means that
people
relate
to one another no longer as doers, but as owners (or non-owners) of
the done (seen now as a thing divorced from doing). Relations between
people exist as relations between things, and people no longer exist
as doers but as the passive bearers of things.
This
separation of doers from doing and hence from themselves is variously
referred
to in the literature as alienation (the young Marx), fetishism (the
older Marx), reification (Lukács), discipline (Foucault) or
identification (Adorno). All of these terms make it clear that
power-over cannot be understood as something external to us, but that
it reaches into every aspect of our existence. All of these terms
point to a rigidification of life, a damming of the social flow of
doing, a closure of possibilities.
Doing
is converted into being: this is the core of power-over. Whereas
doing
means
that we are and are not, the breaking of doing means that the ‘and
are not’ is torn away. We are left just with ‘we are’:
identification. ‘We are not’ is either forgotten or treated as
mere dreaming. Possibility is torn from us. Time is homogenised. The
future is now the extension of the present, the past the preparation
for the present. All doing, all movement, is contained within the
extension of what is. It might be nice to dream of a world worthy of
humanity, but that is just a dream: this is the way things are. The
rule of power-over is the rule of ‘that is the way things are’,
the rule of identity.
7.
We participate in the breaking of our own doing, the construction of
our own
subordination.
As
doers separated from our own doing, we re-create our own
subordination. As
workers
we produce the capital that subordinates us. As university teachers,
we play an active part in the identification of society, in the
transformation of doing into being.
When
we define, classify or quantify, or when we hold that the aim of
science is to
understand
society as it is, or when we pretend to study society objectively, as
though it were an object separate from us, we actively participate in
the negation of doing, in the separation of subject and object, in
the divorcing of doer from done.
- There is no symmetry between power-to and power-over.
Power-over
is the breaking and negation of doing. It is the active and repeated
negation
of the social flow of doing, of the we who constitute ourselves
through social doing. To think that the conquest of power-over can
lead to the emancipation of that which it negates is absurd.
Power-to
is social. It is the constitution of the 'we', the practice of the
mutual
recognition
of dignity.
The
movement of power-to against power-over should not be conceived as
counter-power
(a term which suggests a symmetry between power and counter-power)
but rather as anti-power (a term which, for me, a complete a-symmetry
between power and our struggle).
III
- Power-over appears to penetrate us so deeply that the only possible solution seems to be the intervention of a force from outside. This is no solution at all.
It
is not difficult to reach highly pessimistic conclusions about
present society.
The
injustices and the violence and the exploitation scream at us, and
yet there seems to be no possible way out. Power-over seems to
penetrate every aspect of our lives so deeply that it is hard to
imagine the ‘revolutionary masses’ once dreamed of. In the past,
the deep penetration of capitalist domination led many to see the
solution in terms of the leadership of a vanguard party, but this
proved to be no solution at all, as it simply replaced one form of
power-over with another.
The
easiest answer is pessimistic disillusion. The initial scream of rage
at the
horrors
of capitalism is not abandoned, but we learn to live with it. We do
not become supporters of capitalism, but we accept that there is
nothing that can be done about it.
Disillusion
is a falling into identification, an acceptance that what is, is; an
active
participation,
then, in the separation of doing and done.
10.
The only way to break the apparently closed circle of power is by
seeing that the
transformation
of power-to into power-over is a process which necessarily implies
the
existence of its opposite: fetishisation implies anti-fetishisation.
Most
discussions of alienation (fetishism, reification, discipline,
identification and
so
on) treat it as though it were an accomplished fact. They treat the
forms of capitalist social relations as though they were established
at the dawn of capitalism and will continue until capitalism is
replaced by another mode of social organisation. In other words,
existence is separated from constitution: the constitution of
capitalism is located in the historical past, its present existence
is assumed to be stable. Such a view can only lead to a deep
pessimism.
If,
however, we see the separation of doing and done not as an
accomplished fact
but
as a process, then the world begins to change. The very fact that we
speak of
alienation
means that alienation cannot be complete. If separation, alienation
(etc) is
understood
as a process, then this implies that its course is not
pre-determined, that the transformation of power-to into power-over
is always open, always at issue. A process implies a movement of
becoming, implies that that which is in process (alienation) is and
is not. Alienation, then, is a movement against its own negation,
against anti-alienation. The existence of alienation implies the
existence of anti-alienation. The existence of power-over implies the
existence of anti-power-over, or, in other words, the movement of
emancipation of power-to. That which exists in the form of its
negation, that which exists in the mode of being denied, really
exists, in spite of its negation, as the negation of the process of
denial. Capitalism is based on the denial of power-to, of humanity,
of creativity, of dignity: but that does not mean that these cease to
exist. As the Zapatistas have shown us, dignity exists in spite of
its own negation. It does not stand on its own, but exists in the
only form in which it can exist in this society, as struggle against
its own negation. Power-to exists too: not as an island within a sea
of power-over, but in the only form in which it can exist, as
struggle against its own negation. Freedom too exists, not in the way
that liberals present it, as something independent of social
antagonisms, but in the only way it can exist in a society
characterised by relations of domination, as struggle against that
domination.
The
real, material existence of that which exists in the form of its own
negation, is the basis of hope.
11.
The possibility of changing society radically depends on the material
force of
that
which exists in the mode of being denied.
The
material force of the negated can be seen in a number of ways.
Firstly,
it can be seen in the infinite number of struggles which do not aim
at
winning
power-over others, but simply at asserting our own power-to, our own
resistance against being dominated by others. These take many
different forms, from open rebellion to struggles to gain or defend
control over the labour process, or the processes of health or
education, to the more fragmented, often silent, assertions of
dignity (by children or women) within the home. The struggle for
dignity, for that which is denied by existing society, can be seen
too in many forms that are not overtly political, in literature, in
music, in fairy tales. The struggle against inhumanity is ubiquitous,
for it is implicit in our very existence as humans.
Secondly,
the force of the negated can be seen in the dependence of power-over
upon
that which it negates. Those whose power-to lies in their capacity
to tell others what to do always depend for their existence on the
doing of those others. The whole history of domination can be seen as
the struggle of the powerful to liberate themselves from their
dependence on the powerless. The transition from feudalism to
capitalism can be seen in this light, not just as the struggle of the
serfs to free themselves from the lords, but as the struggle of the
lords to free themselves from their serfs by converting their power
into money and so into capital. The same search for freedom from the
workers can be seen in the introduction of machinery, or in the
massive conversion of productive capital into money capital, which
plays such an important part in contemporary capitalism. In each
case, the flight of the powerful from the doers is in vain. There is
no way in which power-over can be anything other than the
metamorphosis of power-to. There is no way in which the powerful can
escape from their dependence upon the powerless.
This
dependence manifests itself, thirdly, in the instability of the
powerful, in the
tendency
of capital to crisis. Capital’s flight from labour, through the
replacement of
labour
by machines and by its conversion into money, is confronted by its
ultimate
dependence
upon labour (that is, upon its capacity to convert human doing into
abstract value-producing labour) in the form of falling rates of
profit. What manifests itself in crisis is the force of that which
capital denies, namely non-subordinate power-to-do.
- Revolution is urgent but uncertain, a question and not an answer.
Orthodox-Marxist
theories sought to win certainty over to the side of revolution,
arguing
that historical development led inevitably to the creation of a
communist society. This is fundamentally misconceived, because there
can be nothing certain about the creation of a self-determining
society. Certainty can only be on the side of domination. Certainty
is to be found in the homogenisation of time, in the freezing of
doing into being. Self-determination is inherently uncertain. The
death of the old certainties is to be welcomed as a liberation.
For
the same reasons, revolution cannot be understood as an answer, but
only as a
question,
as an exploration in the creation of dignity. Asking we walk.