A
Path Through the Embers and into the Agora?
-
Notes on the Necessity for our Democratic Imagination to Take Better Measure of
the World
Richard Pithouse
Achille Mbembe has argued that the rendering of human beings as waste
by the interface of racism and capitalism in South Africa means that “for the
democratic project to have any future at all, it should necessarily take the
form of a conscious attempt to retrieve
life and 'the human' from a history of waste”. He adds that “the concepts
of 'the human', or of 'humanism', inherited from the West will not suffice. We
will have to take seriously the anthropological embeddedness of such terms in
long histories of "the human" as waste.” Mbembe is not the first to
want to hold on to the idea of the human in the face of the systemic denial of
the full and equal humanity of all people but to insist that the idea of the
human needs to be delinked from what Aimé Césaire
called 'pseudo-humanism' – colonial particularities masquerading as universal. Césaire aspired to “a true humanism....a
humanism made to the measure of the world”. Steve Biko envisioned a “true
humanity”.
The idea that progress requires that some humans should be rendered as
waste was central to the first stirrings of modernity. In 1764 John Locke,
sometimes referred to the 'father of liberalism', took the view that lands
that, where ever they may be in the world, were still governed under an idea of
a right to the commons rather than as private property mediated by money were
'waste' – 'waste' that could and should be redeemed by expropriation. One
consequence of this, as Vinay Gidwani and Rajyashree Reddy have noted, is that
for Locke, 'waste' lies outside of the ethical ambit of civil society. Locke
was a particularly brutal figure - a theorist of slavery, genocide, colonialism
and the workhouse. He thought that children should enter the workhouse at the
age of three. But he was not an aberration within liberal thought. After all
John Stuart Mill, often seen as a gentler figure, entered the East India
Company at the age of 17 and was committed to colonialism throughout his life.
He began his reflections on liberty in 1859 with the disclaimer that “we may
leave out of consideration those backward states of society in which the race
itself may be considered as in its nonage …. Despotism is a legitimate mode of
government in dealing with barbarians.”
The historical practice of liberalism was certainly emancipatory for the
English bourgeoisie from which it emerged but, beginning in Ireland, it
simultaneously produced what Domenico Losurdo describes as “exclusion,
de-humanization and even terror” for millions of others.
In 1842 Karl Marx, a young man with a PhD in
Philosophy, was wrestling with the German failure to repeat the French
Revolution. He quickly realised that making the world more philosophical would
require that philosophy be made more worldly, that it take its place in the
actual struggles in the world. As Stathis Kouvelakis has shown Marx saw that
the state and capital both tended towards a repression of the political and,
looking for what he called 'a third element', a constituent power, he first
turned to the press arguing that the “free press is the ubiquitous vigilant eye
of a people's soul...the spiritual mirror in which a people can see itself, and
self-examination is the first condition of wisdom.” Marx hoped that “an
association of free human beings who educate one another” in an expanding
public sphere could subordinate the state to rational, public discussion in a
process of ongoing democratisation. But when, in the following year, the
newspaper that he edited was banned Marx turned his attention away from the
elite public sphere towards “suffering human beings who think” and to the hope
that “making participation in politics, and therefore real struggles, the
starting point of our criticism” could provide new grounds for commitment to
democracy as a process of democratisation.
The philosophical dogma of the day, which, from London to Johannesburg, remains the dogma of our own time, had argued that as a large mass of people sank into poverty they would become a rabble, a threat to society. But Marx insisted that “only one thing is characteristic, namely that lack of property and the estate of direct labour...form not so much an estate of civil society as the ground upon which its circles rest and move.” Marx, always refusing to hold up abstract ideas of an alternative society to which actually existing struggles should conform, looked to the real movement of the working class, the male working class of parts of Western Europe, for principles to orientate future struggle and the material force to be able to realise them. True to his turn to a philosophy of immanence he insisted that theory, philosophy, can become a material force when it is formulated from the perspective of the oppressed and becomes part of their constituent movement. But he insisted that for this happen it must be radical because “To be radical is to grasp things by the root. But for man, the root is man himself.” Communism, he insisted, is “fully developed humanism”.
The philosophical dogma of the day, which, from London to Johannesburg, remains the dogma of our own time, had argued that as a large mass of people sank into poverty they would become a rabble, a threat to society. But Marx insisted that “only one thing is characteristic, namely that lack of property and the estate of direct labour...form not so much an estate of civil society as the ground upon which its circles rest and move.” Marx, always refusing to hold up abstract ideas of an alternative society to which actually existing struggles should conform, looked to the real movement of the working class, the male working class of parts of Western Europe, for principles to orientate future struggle and the material force to be able to realise them. True to his turn to a philosophy of immanence he insisted that theory, philosophy, can become a material force when it is formulated from the perspective of the oppressed and becomes part of their constituent movement. But he insisted that for this happen it must be radical because “To be radical is to grasp things by the root. But for man, the root is man himself.” Communism, he insisted, is “fully developed humanism”.
But
there were moments in his life when Karl Marx took the view that colonialism
would be an ultimately redemptive force thereby implicitly rendering the
majority of actually existing people and economies as waste
in the name of a shared future to come. Kevin
Anderson's recent book Marx at the
Margins provides a useful analysis
of the way in which Marx's thought evolved during the course of his life and
shows, in particular, that he came to reject the idea of colonialism as a
progressive force and began to look at communal modes of life, outside of its
reach, and the reach of capital, as potential sites of progressive movement. Aditya
Mukherjee has also done important work on how Marx moved away from his initial
view of colonialism as an ultimately historically progressive force. Nonetheless
there are still cases such as, for instance, in West Bengal, where ongoing
dispossession, and the rendering of people as waste, has been justified in the
name of a form of Marxism that, wielded by the state, continues to see the
enclosure of the commons and proletarianisation as the royal road to a
socialist future.
At home, in Europe, Marx, in the first
half of his life, spoke of the 'lumpen-proletariat',
the urban poor living outside of wage labour, with astonishing vitriol. Marx first coined the term in The German
Ideology – a text that was written
in 1846 amidst the crop failure, escalating urbanisation and first stirrings of
political ferment that would soon explode into the European spring of 1848. It,
tellingly, moves from the assumption that it is production rather than, say, as
Aristotle would have it, the capacity for speech that distinguishes the human
from the animal. The term 'lumpen-proletariat'
is usually translated as the 'ragged proletariat' but the word 'lumpen' meant both ragged and knave and
it has been suggested that Marx had the second use of the word in mind. In the Communist Manifesto of 1848 he, with Friedrich Engles,wrote of “The 'dangerous class', the social scum, that passively rotting
mass thrown off by the lowest layers of the old society”. Four years later, in
the 18th Brumaire, he railed against the “scum, offal, refuse
of all classes”.
Ernesto Laclau shows that,
at this point in Marx's work, the proletariat is strictly delimited from the lumpen-proletariat
in order to affirm its position
within capitalist development with the result that the lumpen-proletariat is
given the status of the pure outside and its “expulsion from the field of
historicity is the very condition of a pure interiority”. In other words the
virtue of workers, male workers, is asserted against the dissolution of the
urban poor. But when he wrote Capital,
fifteen years after the 18th Brumaire, Marx took a far less hostile view
arguing that:
it is capitalist accumulation itself that
constantly produces, and produces indeed in direct relation with its own energy
and extent, a relatively redundant working population, i.e. a population which
is superfluous to capital's average requirements for its own valorization, and
is therefore a surplus population.
He also presents the
“combination between the employed and unemployed” as both a way for workers to
combat the rendering of their own place within capitalist production as
precarious and a real threat to the logic of capitalist production that, via
the logic of supply and demand, relies on the existence of a large group of people
without an independent livelihood or a wage to drive wages down. Here Marx’s
political imagination can see a positive role for the urban poor, although he
still thinks of labour solely in terms of work performed by men in the factory.
He writes that for the worker capitalist social relations “transform his
life-time into working-time, and drag his wife and child beneath the juggernaut
of capital’. Silvia Federici, who we were honoured to have here at Rhodes last
month, has shown not just that the home is also a site of labour, largely
performed by women, but also that this labour enables the reproduction of the
work force on which capitalism depends. Marx also continues to imagine political
agency solely in terms of struggles between labour or potential labour and
capital. Nonetheless Marxism, as both doctrine and political culture, often
retains a deep current of hostility to the urban poor and often sustains a fetish
of the industrial working class, often imagined as male, as the only subject
capable of emancipatory political action. In contemporary South Africa it is not
uncommon for Marxists, in and out of the academy, and including in seminar
discussions here at Rhodes, to dismiss, on an a priori basis - and without any attempt to investigate a
particular political event, sequence or organisation - any prospect of
progressive action on the part of the urban poor. Jeff Peires, for instance, has
invoked Marx and the idea of the lumpen
proletariat to reject, out of hand, the prospect of progressive organisation
and mobilisation on the part of the unemployed in Grahamstown. Jimmy Adisina has
also invoked the idea of the lumpen
proletariat in a way that compounds rather than contests the production of
people as waste.
Colonial
discourses about race and the urban poor were enmeshed from the early 1800s.
Engels followed the bourgeois thought of the day declaring the lumpen
proletariat to be a “race...robbed of all humanity, degraded, reduced
morally and physically to bestiality”. At one point Engels repeats one of the
key tropes of the bourgeois thought of the time, a trope that, in a racialised
form, also became central to colonial ideology – that the urban poor are those
“who do not wish to work”. Nicholas Thorburn concludes that “Marx and
Engels' most vehement assaults are saved for those who seem to revel in
surviving outside productive relations”.
As
Kristin Ross has shown with her characteristic élan the Paris Commune of 1871,
an urban revolt that became a decisive moment in the formation of the modern
left, and continues to carry particular import for many radical approaches to
the urban question, also became a decisive moment in the political investment
in the idea of the good worker, a man, by the modern left. She suggests that
this was largely in response to right wing diatribes, often highly gendered,
that presented the politicised urban poor in monstrous terms. The Parisian elites at the time, along with the usual claims that
criminals and foreign agents were behind the uprising, claims that are all too
familiar to us in contemporary South Africa, also pointed, amidst a full-scale
moral panic, to the perversely gendered image of the Communard as a woman, a
'petroleuse' - a “bloodthirsty, slothful, drunken prostitute”. Marx’s political investment in ‘working men’,
and in particular factory workers, in response to a political event, a
municipal revolution largely constituted around the neighbourhood rather than
the factory, and that was, Manuel Castells argues, “decisively an action by the
women”, has left its mark on the common sense of the left.
This fetish of the male worker as the only
credible revolutionary subject is often apparent in dissident and more
democratic currents of Marxism. In her reflections on the Russian Revolution,
published in 1918, Rosa Luxemburg, often seen, and for good reason, as a
democratic alternative to Vladimir Lenin, presented the 'lumpen proletariat', under the heading of “The Struggle Against
Corruption”, and with reference to terms like 'degeneration' and 'sickness', as
a “problem to be reckoned with”, an “enemy and instrument of
counter-revolution” requiring the 'healing' and 'purifying' rays of a
revolutionary sun. In an earlier
intervention, The Mass Strike, she had written that “Anarchism has become in the Russian Revolution, not the
theory of the struggling proletariat, but the ideological signboard of the
counterrevolutionary lumpen proletariat,
who, like a school of sharks, swarm in the wake of the battleship of the
revolution. And therewith the historical career of anarchism is well-nigh
ended.”
But classical anarchism mirrored rather than
opposed the objectification of the urban poor surviving outside of formal
employment. While Marx saw proletarianisation as enabling revolutionary agency
Mikhail Bakunin saw it as destroying revolutionary agency which, for him, was
rooted in the peasant commune and its insurrectionary traditions and
various groups in the cities that had not been subordinated to the discipline
of work. Bakunin sustained Marx and Engel's objectification of the urban poor
while inverting its logic to conclude that “in them and only in them [the lumpen-proletariat], and not
in the bourgeois strata of workers, are there crystallized the entire
intelligence and power of the coming Social Revolution. A popular insurrection,
by its very nature, is instinctive, chaotic, and destructive”. As Thorburn
notes Bakunin, “in a fashion not so different from Marx's account of lumpen
'spontaneity'”, assumes that the lumpen-proletariat carries a
“transhistorical instinctual rage”. There is no space here for a politics
rooted in organisation, worked out via the use of reason and expressed as
speech.
There are other lacunae
in the classic texts of the modern left. For Walter Benjamin, writing in 1940,
the year that he, in flight from the Nazis, took his own life on the border
between Spain and France, the wreckage upon wreckage that undergirds the
'storm' of modern progress erected the elegance of the Parisian arcades, the
ancestor of today's mall, on the foundation of a permanent state of emergency.
But while crude material need was systemically unmet the working class in
Germany could still assume that being swept into the factory was, nonetheless,
a movement with the current of history, with the “fall of the stream”, in which
it would soon take its rightful place. The
factory appears as a step on the way from the commons to socialism. But in the
colonised world people were not only expropriated and proletarianised. People
were also turned into members of races in a world that was, Frantz Fanon wrote
in 1961, the last year of his life, “cut in two”, divided into “compartments
.... inhabited by different species”.
In the famous equation of Aime Césaire, Fanon's high school
teacher and one of the great poets of the last century, “colonization
= 'thingification'”. Césaire,
writing in 1955, insists that in the colony 'the storm' is more about what has
been trampled, confiscated, wiped out and brought into new regimes of abuse in
“a circuit of mutual services and complicity” than any sense of hard won but
ultimately redemptive universal progress. Here neither the living nor the dead can be redeemed
by a modernity in which capital makes concessions to society in a double
movement, or a revolutionary proletariat seizes the engines of progress for
itself, until racism is abolished and humanity known under a generic
appellation. But the sorry state of the postcolony where, as Fanon warned,
national consciousness has seldom attained “political and social
consciousness”, makes it clear that while the abolition of racism is a
necessary condition for the achievement of a generic humanity it is not, on its
own, a sufficient condition. In fact it’s clear that colonialism and
anti-colonial nationalism have often shared a view of the subaltern, as Partha
Chatterjee writes of the peasantry in India, “as an object of their strategies,
to be acted upon, controlled, and appropriated within their respective
structures of state power.” Chatterjee also notes that elite nationalist
thought excludes the subaltern from the domain of reason and argues that
“Nowhere in the world has nationalism qua nationalism challenged the legitimacy
of the marriage between Reason and capital.” Both the expulsion of the
subaltern from the domain of reason by nationalist elites, in and out of the
state, and the conception of the subaltern as an object to be acted on from
above, which is also central to the logic of some forms of left vanguardism,
including those organised in NGOs and groupuscles of various sorts, are
familiar to us in South Africa.
Chatterjee has sought
to introduce some conceptual categories that can shift the discussion of what
he calls 'popular politics in most of the world' on to a rational terrain. In
his estimation shack dwellers, living outside of the law are not just subject
to stigmatisation but are also structurally excluded from the agora. They are,
he argues, “only tenuously, and then even then ambiguously and contextually,
rights-bearing citizens in the sense imagined by the constitution. They are
not, therefore, proper members of civil society and are not regarded as such by
the state”. Chatterjee notes that politics conducted outside of civil society,
outside of “the zone of legitimate political discourse”, is often just
dismissed as “lumpen culture” amidst fears that “politics has been taken over
by mobs and criminals”. Again this is
something that we are very familiar with in South Africa. And there have been occasions
when the left has read the entry of the subaltern subject into the agora with
forms of panic and hostility, sometimes clearly racialised, that mirror those
of the most crudely unreflective forms of ordinary bourgeois thought. Chatterjee
argues that it makes better sense to see the zone of engagement outside of
civil society as what he calls 'political society', a space in which people may
“transgress the strict lines of legality in struggling to live and work” but
are, nonetheless, engaged in real forms of politics, some of which can enable
“actual expansion of the freedoms of people”. Aditya Nigam, who is not
uncritical of Chatterjee, has written that Chatterjee's “notion of ‘political
society’ has provided an unprecedented opening, a possibility – that of
thinking the ‘unthinkable’”.
In Texaco, his fabulously inventive
novel about a shack settlement in Martinique, Patrick Chamoiseau writes of a
“proletariat without factories, workshops, and work, and without bosses, in the
muddle of odd jobs, drowning in survival and leading an existence like a path
through embers”. But Texaco is also a novel of struggle, of struggle
with the 'persistence of Sisyphus' - struggle to hold a soul together in the
face of relentless destruction amidst a “disaster of asbestos, tin sheets,
crates, mud tears, blood, police”. It is a novel of barricades, police and
fire, a struggle to “call forth the poet in the urban planner”, a struggle to
'enter City' . It's also about the need to “hold on, hold on, and moor the
bottom of your heart in the sand of deep freedom.”
The theoretical project, undertaken in and
around the academy, of working towards the assertion of a more genuinely
universal humanism and a more genuinely universal emancipatory horizon – 'the
sand of deep freedom' - is one thing. The political project of affirming an
equal humanity amidst relentless destruction and waste with 'the persistence of
Sisyphus' is another. It is not that often that they are brought together. One
reason for this is that it is a common feature of a wide range of polities that
the damned of the earth, people who may be seen as populations to be managed by
the state and NGOs but who live and work outside of the parameters established
as legitimate by bourgeois society, are not welcome in a shared agora.
Indeed it is common for their very appearance in the agora as rational
speaking beings rather than as silent victims requesting help from their
masters, or a cheering mass performing fealty to their masters, to be received
as illicit – as violent, criminal, fraudulent and consequent to malevolent
conspiracy – even when their presence takes the form of nothing other than
rational speech. This is as common in states that aspire to liberal democracy
as it is in states governed by an authoritarian nationalism - be it inflected
with ideas of the right or the left. It's also equally common when the masters
in question are in the state, NGOs (across the political spectrum) or the left
– understood, in Alain Badiou's terms, as the set of people that claim “that
they are the only ones able to provide 'social movements' with a 'political
perspective' ”. Jacques Rancière is quite right to insist that, from the
ancient world until today: “The war of the poor and the rich is also a war over
the very existence of politics. The dispute over the count of the poor as
people, and of the people as the community, is a dispute about the existence of
politics through which politics occurs”. We need to be clear that while it is
true that, since Plato, it has often been thought that workers should keep to
their place and function it is also true that during the last century workers
won a political place, a subordinate place to be sure, in many societies. And
as we know all too well the worker who steps on to the political stage outside
of authorised forms of organisation and representation can very quickly appear
as criminal or as a dupe of someone else's conspiracy to the state and civil
society. But there is often a significant degree to which the urban poor, and
especially people people who live and work outside of the law, are cast out of
civil society, and out of the count of who has a right to the political, in a
way that is far more acute than that of worker who lives and works within the
law. This situation has often been intensely compounded when people who have to
make their lives on 'a path through embers' have also been raced.
There
is a long history, across space and time, of people being objectified in a
manner that refuses to recognise their speech as speech or to take their
political capacities seriously. In Silencing
the Past Michel-Rolph Trouillot, a brilliant historian who died last year,
examines the reception of the Haitian Revolution of 1804. He showed that the
idea of African slaves winning a revolutionary war for their freedom against
the great European powers of the day was simply unimaginable - ‘unthinkable’ -
in the most globally powerful sites of authorised intellectual authority at the
time. He notes that the Haitian Revolution “constituted a sequence for which
not even the extreme left in France or in England had a conceptual frame of
reference”. Trouillot goes on to argue that “the narrative structures of
Western historiography have not broken with the ontological order of the
Renaissance” and concludes that “This exercise of power is much more important
than the alleged conservative or liberal adherence of the historians involved”.
Today we can speak of a ‘silencing
of the present’. Human beings continue to become objects to others, either
invisible or hyper-present, their faces distorted into caricature or worn into
nothingness by the enduring weight of the economic, spatial and symbolic
division of the world in accordance with what Trouillot terms “an ontology, an
implicit organization of the world and its inhabitants”.
There
has been, and, with important exceptions, often continues to be, a silencing of the struggles of the urban poor,
struggles in which women have often been at the forefront, even within theories
of collective emancipation. In the metropolitan ghetto, defined by Loïc
Wacquant as a “distinctive, spatially based, concatenation of mechanisms of
ethnoracial closure and control”, what Wacquant calls 'territorial
stigmatization' has been profoundly inflected by race. The idea that spatial
divisions, which are also sociological, must also be ontological has frequently
been part of the unexamined common sense of the postcolony. For instance Obika
Gray writes that in Jamacia in the 1970s the “mobilized urban poor remained a
morally discredited, socially isolated and culturally stigmatized group”.
The
tendency to read the intersection of spatial and sociological realities in ontological
terms often endures across time and through different political regimes. In
1976 Janice Perlman famously argued that the myth of the marginality, of the
moral degradation of shack dwellers in Rio was produced by the “constant
attempt of those in power to blame the poor for their position because of
deviant attitudes, masking the unwillingness of the powerful to share their
privilege”. She noted that “the political left is also influenced to some
extent by the myths of marginality” and concluded the myth was “anchored in
people's minds by roots that will remain unshaken by any theoretical
criticism”. Almost forty years later Raúl Zibechi reports that: “The Latin
American left regard the poor peripheries as pockets of crime, drug
trafficking, and violence; spaces where chaos and the law of the jungle reign.
Distrust takes the place of understanding. There is not the slightest
difference in perspective between left and right on this issue”.
This
can be compounded by the catastrophic and still poisonous history of race as a
tool of domination. Achille Mbembe begins On
the Postcolony by noting that “Speaking rationally about Africa is not
something that has ever come naturally”. V.Y. Mudimbe notes that anxieties
about the African presence in the modern world have often been particular
concerned with the urban African: “Marginality designates the intermediate
space between the so-called African tradition and the projected modernity of
colonialism. It is apparently an urbanized space.” The university’s pretensions
to science, or academic rigour, offer no automatic immunity from the widespread
inability to consider Africa, and sometimes, in particular urban Africa,
rationally.
In
1952, in his first published essay, The
North African Syndrome, Fanon, then twenty seven years old, argued that in
France migrant workers from North Africa were “hidden beneath a social truth”,
“thingified and “dissolve(d) on the basis of an idea” within French science. He
was particularly critical of the view that the North African was “a thing
tossed into the great sound and fury” which he described as “manifestly and
abjectly disingenuous” as it functioned to mask both the reality of an inhuman
system that treated people as objects and the humanity of the people in
question. The philosopher Lewis Gordon, who will take up the Nelson Mandela
Professorship at Rhodes University next year – and whose work on ‘illicit
appearance’ speaks well to some of the issues I am raising here - makes a
similar point in his sustained reading of W.E.B. Du Bois's essay The Study of the Negro Problem over the
last decade or so. The essential lesson that Gordon draws from his reading of
Du Bois is that there is a profound difference between studying oppressed
people as 'problem people', an approach that implicitly assumes that the
broader system is essentially just and that there is something lacking in
people who inhabit its underside, and studying oppressed people as people that
have been subject to oppression and confront a particular set of problems
consequent to that experience. A concept like the 'lumpen-proletariat', or 'the lumpen'
which has been borrowed from Marx by Mbembe, and seized on from Mbembe with
some enthusiasm by liberals like Alistair Sparks is, when used uncritically and
without very careful qualification, plainly more suited to the first mode of study
than it is to the second.
Around
the world, contemporary struggles by the urban poor are often, via implicit
recourse to an ontological division of the world, subject to contemporary forms
of silencing. For instance in an intervention on the uprising in the Parisian
ghettoes in 2006 Emilio Quadrelli shows the huge gulf between the assumptions, invariably
pejorative, of what Bruno Bosteels calls speculative leftism, delinked from
concrete engagement and “as radical as it is politically inoperative”, and the
realities of the actually existing struggles in the banlieues by the simple but
effective device of juxtaposing theoretical flights of academic fantasy,
ungrounded in any actual experience of participation in popular struggles or
credible research, with interviews with grassroots militants. There are cases
in which a similar method would produce similar results in South Africa. NGOs,
which often set the agenda for the media and academy, can also function to
silence popular political initiative on the part of the urban poor. Peter
Hallward shows that in Haiti NGO power is frequently racialised: “the provision
of white enlightened charity to destitute and allegedly ‘superstitious’ blacks
is part and parcel of an all too familiar neo-colonial pattern”. He notes that
left NGOs tend not to “organize with and among the people …. In the places and
on the terms where the people are strong” but prefer “trivial made-for-media
demonstrations ….. usually attended by tiny groups of 30 or 40 people”. Hallward shows that some of these NGOs, like
Action Aid – now headquartered in Johannesburg, supported the 2004 US backed
coup against an elected government that drew much of its support from the urban
poor. His critique extends beyond NGOs and includes the small political
organisation Batay Ouvriye, a tiny political organisation that is, “like any
number of neo-Trotskyite sects …. militant and inconsequential in equal
measure”, but has nonetheless been prominent on the international left and
which produced slander against popular forms of political mobilisation as
virulent as anything produced by the right. This became, he concludes,
“invaluable propaganda for the sector of civil society” most committed to
legitimating the US backed coup against a popular and elected government. Hallward’s
account of how popular struggles in Haiti have been received by elites in NGOs
and small political sects has striking points of connection with recent South
African experiences. In both the cases
discussed by Quadrelli and Hallward it becomes clear that a priori ontological assumptions are sometimes given more
explanatory weight than empirical investigations.
Perhaps there needs to be a return to Mao's dictum ‘No investigation no right to speak’ that was appropriated
in Paris in 1968 with considerable intellectual and political consequence.
The rendering of people as 'waste' takes on a particularly
acute intensity in South Africa. As Giovanni Arrighi et al note “the South(ern) African experience (is) … a
paradigmatic outlier case of accumulation by dispossession”. Gill Hart has
argued that here the extent of dispossession is an important factor driving the
inability of the economy to create employment. The scale of what Marx called
'immiseration' extends far beyond that of any process that could be argued to
be functional to the economy in so far as it constitutes a 'reserve army of
labour'. Large numbers of people are simply economically redundant. And for
many people labour, whether or not it is accompanied by a wage, is undertaken
on a precarious and often highly exploitative basis outside of the formal
economy and the legal protections that, often more in principle than in
practice, regular labour in that sphere. This economic bifurcation is being actively
compounded by the persistence of a profoundly unequal and inadequate education
system. Moreover the rendering of people as waste is increasingly being built
into the materiality of our cities in the form of the peripheral housing
developments and the transit camp – zones of exclusion, suffering and
stigmatisation - both of which are widely referred to in popular discourse via
metaphors that speak to contemporary forms of 'development' as banishment,
incarceration and the rendering of human beings as rubbish and as animals.
Trade unions continue, sometimes militantly, to contest the terms
on which labour engages with capital. But the community has, as was the case in
the 1980s, also become a site of intense struggle. The shack settlement has
often been central to this still escalating sequence of struggle the nature and
significance of which is often obscured by the a priori use of descriptive terms like ‘popcorn protests’ or, more
commonly, ‘service delivery protests’. These terms often function to render
protest banal but there is also a whole lexicon that functions to render it
perverse. Across a range of sites of elite power shack dwellers'
political agency is frequently read in terms of external conspiracy,
criminality or some sort of intersection between ignorance and thuggery.
Reports of deliberative and democratic processes on the part of grassroots
militants or researchers who have engaged in long term ethnographic immersion or
participation have been confidently dismissed as, a priori, romantic or
even fraudulent by people who have not conducted any investigation of their
own. Both the ruling African National Congress (ANC) and the Democratic
Alliance (DA) routinely present protest from shack settlements in terms of malevolent
external conspiracy . In March 2013 a Durban newspaper, The Daily News,
ran a story with the headline ‘Shack dwellers invade Durban’. The article,
described the shack dwellers in question as an armed ‘mob’, and as ‘invaders’
and quotes interviewees, local property owners, describing a ‘mad racket’ and
speaking of a ‘tragedy’. The land occupation inciting all this panic had been
organised by long standing residents of the city who had been illegally and
brutally evicted from their homes by the municipality. It was hardly an
invasion of the city. When challenged from below to operate in a more
democratic manner NGO networks have, just like the state, responded with
entirely dishonest allegations of criminality, thuggery or external
manipulation. There are cases where academics have repeated some of the worst
aspects of the sectarian slander, some of it outrightly defamatory, much of it
clearly racialised, against autonomous popular organisation that has emerged
out of the intersection between NGOs and the authoritarian left in South Africa.
But even when academic work has no particular axe to grind it frequently writes
about the urban poor in a manner that draws on all too confidently held
prejudices rather than credible research. For instance Daryl Glaser, in a piece
on the xenophobic and ethnic pogroms of May 2008 that Michael Neocosmos rightly
terms “crass”, simply asserted that “popular democracy in action is not a
pretty sight” and concluded that the pogroms were in fact “profoundly
democratic, albeit in a majoritarian sense”. No mention was made of the popular
organisations, in at least one case deeply democratic, that effectively opposed
xenophobic and ethnic violence. The result is that the reader is left with the
false impression, one that conforms to the most base stereotypes prevalent
amongst elites, that all poor people are xenophobic, violent and incapable of
participation in the agora. In an otherwise valuable article on Jacob
Zuma's rape trial Shireen Hassim writes that:
(T)here is
also a challenge to rebuild relationships horizontally with the leadership of
the social movements, who support Zuma as a ‘pro-poor’ candidate. Despite
their professed commitment to poor women, the new social movements have
revealed themselves as ready to ditch equality rights when ‘more important’
decisions about leadership are debated. Of the major social movements on the
left, only the TAC has sided with women’s organisations. Yet it is not the only
social movement that has a majority female membership – the same is true of the
Anti-Eviction Campaign, the Soweto Electricity Crisis Campaign [sic], and
Abahlali ‘Mjondolo[sic]. These movements, dependent on women for their
grassroots character, seem willing to trade away women’s rights to dignity and
autonomy for short-term political gain.
This author has no inside knowledge of
how the Soweto Electricity Crisis Committee responded to the campaign in
support of Zuma at the time. But it can be affirmed with certainty that neither
the Anti-Eviction Campaign nor Abahlali baseMjondolo ever expressed support for
Zuma in any form. In the latter case the refusal to support Zuma cost the
movement some support in some neighbourhoods, including support from women, and
resulted in it being subject to serious intimidation, including
misrepresentation from a suddenly explicitly ethnicised local ANC as having
'sold out' to its Indian and Xhosa members. This eventually enabled serious
state backed violence against its leading members that was mediated through
ethnic claims. Hassim's gross misrepresentation of the politics in the
Anti-Eviction Campaign and Abahlali baseMjondolo at the time is certainly not
based on any attempt to make sense of empirical realities but it does confirm
to some stereotypes about popular politics. This cannot be held to be
respectful of the dignity and autonomy of the members of these movements, many
of which, including many people in leadership positions in Abahlali
baseMjondolo, were women.
The significance of the shack settlement as a site of politics, and the
shack dweller as a subject of politics, is not a recent development. On the
contrary the shack
settlement became highly politicised in South Africa at various moments during
the last century. These included the mobilisation by the Industrial and
Commercial Workers' Union in Durban in the second half of the 1920s, the
various shack dwellers' movements in Johannesburg in the 1940s, the
contestation for Cato Manor in Durban from the late 1940s until the late 1950s,
and the mass struggles of the 1980s which, in and out of the shack settlement,
often took an urban form. There were moments when insurgent spatial practices
were combined with a broader vision for social change and there were moments
where women’s agency was central to these mobilisations. But, perhaps most
infamously in Cato Manor in 1949 and in Inanda, in Durban, and Crossroads, in
Cape Town, in the 1980s, there were also highly reactionary forms of violent
mobilisation grounded in the opportunities for livelihoods that can be found in
shack settlements and mediated via appeals to ethnicity or the patriarchal
authority of culture. These forms of reactionary mobilisation often aligned
themselves with a repressive state. They have a lot in common with the form of
mobilisation that the ANC has recently sought to incite in Durban in order to
crush independent organisation.
Before the end
of apartheid shack dwellers' struggles were usually subsumed under a
nationalist struggle, or opposition to it, that tended to disavow the
particularity of the shack settlement as a site of habitation and struggle. It
was often assumed that the urban question would be automatically resolved by
the success of the national struggle. However there are clear lines of
continuity in both state and popular practices in the periods before, during
and after apartheid. The state continues to respond to the urban poor in an
exclusionary, authoritarian and often violent manner. It continues, as happened
under apartheid and colonialism, to see dissent from below, whether formally
organised or not, as a result of external conspiracy rather than as what it
says it is. At the same time insurgent spatial practices, sometimes taking the
form of what Asef Bayat calls 'quiet encroachment' and sometimes taking the
form of overtly political mobilisation – like the recent spate of land
occupations named 'Marikana', continue and, at times, continue to offer a
significant challenge to the ability of the state and capital to sustain their
duopoly on urban planning. After apartheid the shack settlement has, again,
become a site of acute political intensity.
The intensity of the shack settlement as a site of contestation plainly
has a lot to do with material factors. It also has a lot to do with the state's
turn in 2004 towards an agenda aimed at the control and eradication rather than
support of shack settlements. The way in the which the state and the ruling
party seek to discipline rather than enable organisation in the shack
settlement is also an important factor. But it also has something to do with
the fact that to step into the shack settlement is to step into the void. This
is not because of any ontological difference amongst the people living there,
or because life there is entirely other at the level of day to day sociality.
It is because it is a site that is not fully inscribed within the laws and
rules through which the state governs society. Because its meaning is not
entirely fixed it is an unstable element of the situation. The unfixed way in
which the shack settlement is indexed to the situation opens opportunity for a
variety of challenges - from above and from below, democratic and
authoritarian, in the name of the political, of tradition, of nationalism and
of private interest, and from the left and the right - to the official order of
things. Of course neither social exclusion, nor the many ways in which it is
resisted, can be reduced to the shack settlement. But there is no question that
it is a site where people's various forms of refusal to accept that they be
rendered as 'waste' have come in to intense and sustained conflict with the
state.
The shack settlement was a
central site for the xenophobic pogroms that swept parts of the country in
2008. It has also been a
central site for most of the formally organised movements to have emerged after
apartheid. The shack settlement has also
been a key site in the
sequence of popular protest that is generally not organised by sustained and
formally constituted social movements. Camalita Naicker, a Masters student here
at Rhodes, is looking at women’s struggles in Marikana. Her work shows that the
shack settlement was an important part of the struggle in Marikana. Benjamin Fogel, who studied here at
Rhodes, has argued that in De Doorns, the centre of the uprising on the farms
in the Western Cape last year, key organisers had been politicised by struggles
for housing and services in the Stofland shack settlement. Women and young
people have often been central to the forms of organisation and mobilisation
that have been developed in the shack settlement which have often been
constituted around the idea of community rather than work. These realities have
not always sat well with forms of politics that - invariably dogmatic, often
authoritarian and uniformly unable to build sustained mass organisation or
mobilisation - operate under the illusory assumption that reality should, in
Antonio Gramsci's words, “conform to [pre-existing] abstract schema”.
Dwelling is fundamental to any existential conception of human being.
And, as Martin Heidegger argued in 1951, “We attain to dwelling, so it seems, only
by means of building”. Given the degree to which direction
from donor and state agendas has ensured that much of the academic and NGO
writing about housing and the broader urban question in contemporary South
Africa is entirely technocratic this assertion of the existential aspect of
dwelling, which has tremendous popular resonance – often framed in the language
of dignity, is invaluable. Housing is
not solely a matter of a material need and the degree to which its provision is
effective is not solely a quantitative question. It is also, as has so often
been asserted in struggle, a matter of dignity.
But modes of building and dwelling are not
solely inflected by existential choice. The capacity to build for oneself is
dependent on access to resources – whether from a wage, other form of income or
a commons – and the regulation of the right to build, or to occupy buildings,
has frequently been one of the mechanisms by which people are classified into
putative types and by which participation in the agora,
economic well-being and access to
physical security has been mediated. Buildings, and the lines of force that cut
through their agglomeration, shape space and constitute a considerable part of
the social situation in which dwelling takes form. Both economic and political
inequality and forms of opposition to exclusion and domination, be they in the
form of popular action – be it insurgent or defensive, openly and collectively
confrontational or quieter and more personal forms of disobedience - or state reforms,
have often been concretised in the manner in which the world is built and the
social logic of building sustained by armed force in the hands of the state and
the market, barricades in the hands of popular forces and all kinds of less
dramatic forms of routine social regulation and contestation.
The intensity of
the shack settlement as a site of politics is not, at all, unique to South
Africa. There is a similar intensity, that often draws on a
repertoire of tactics that, like the road blockade marked by burning tyres,
have become part of an international grammar of protest in many countries
across the global South. In India and Kenya the shack settlement has been a
site of catastrophic religious and ethnic mobilisation. But it has also recently been an site of progressive
politics that, in countries like Bolivia, Haiti and Venezuela, has made
important national interventions with international consequences. Account of
the Egyptian uprising based on credible research rather than lazy assumptions
about the power of social media are increasingly pointing to the role of the
urban poor. Raúl Zibechi take the view that: ”If a specter is haunting the
Latin American elites at the beginning of the twenty-first century, it is for
sure living in the peripheries of the large urban cities. The main challenges
to the dominant system in the last two decades have emerged from the heart of
the poor urban peripheries.”
In South Africa,
as is common elsewhere, the shack settlement has also become a deeply contested
space onto which elite fears about crime, immigration, disease, and political
and social insubordination, sometimes gendered, are projected with increasing
virulence. In some cases it is a site of spatial exclusion that is functional
to capital, and bourgeois society more generally, as it enables low wage
labour, usually precariously employed, to be housed at no cost to the state or
capital. But there are also cases where it provides a genuine challenge to the
sanctity of private property and spatial segregation. When shack settlements
are spatially insurgent they often enable access to opportunities of various
sources, and in particular those relating to livelihoods, and to institutions,
like schools.
At the same time
as all sorts of anxieties are projected onto the shack settlement political
parties and NGOs are involved in active competition to capture these spaces and
to be able to represent their inhabitants as obedient partisans of their
projects. The result is a strange bifurcation in the stereotypes projected onto
shack settlements and shack dwellers. When they are seen as a threat to
bourgeois society – across the political spectrum - shack settlements appear,
as Fanon wrote as “places of ill fame peopled by women and men of evil repute”.
But when their inhabitants have, or can be made to appear to have accepted the
tutelage of an NGO or a clientelist relation to a political party they are more
likely to appear as the long suffering but patient and noble poor. In both
cases the shack dweller appears as other-worldly and certainly does not appear
as a person who thinks or who is worthy or indeed capable of independent
participation in civil society. On the contrary it is routinely assumed that
civil society is a space in which, as Marx observed with regard to French
peasants: “They cannot represent themselves, they must be represented.
Their representative must at the same time appear as their master, as an
authority over them”. The result of this is that the shack settlement routinely appears as a space from
which, to appropriate Jacques Rancière’s words, “only groans or cries
expressing suffering, hunger or anger could emerge, but not actual speech
demonstrating a shared aisthesis”. Despite the persistence of the shack
settlement as a site of politics there is an enduring inability amongst elites,
across the political spectrum, to recognise political agency in the shack
settlement. No matter how articulate the subaltern may be there is a systemic
inability to recognise her speech as speech in elite publics. This is as true for the state as it is for
much of the media, professional civil society and the academy, including, in
both the latter cases, their left edges.
Ever since the
shack settlement became a site of politics after apartheid, and from
Johannesburg, to Durban, Cape Town and innumerable small towns, it has,
irrespective of the language that people are speaking, become common to hear
people ground their right to disobedience in an affirmation of their humanity.
Of course other discourses are also mobilised including citizenship,culture,
loyalty to the ANC and histories of struggle. But, although popular politics is
a certainly a dynamic space the affirmation of humanity as a foundation for a
challenge to elites of various sorts has been striking. The years of protest
from shack settlements around the country have won many small victories but
they have never come close to forcing the state, capital and civil society to
accept a fundamental democratisation of the urban regime. However they have
constituted the urban poor as political actors and, despite relentless attempts
by various elite actors to technicise the political, to politicise aspects of
the ongoing production of people as waste.
There
is a rich tradition of thought that, in Césaire's phrase cited at the outset, reaches towards “a humanism made to the measure of
the world”. This thought has
sought to extend the category of those that count as fully human and to oppose
ontological explanations for invisibility, exclusion or subordination with
political explanations. Some of it has, as Mbembe writes in a luminous
essay on what he calls the “force and power” of the “metamorphic thought” of
Fanon, “the brightness of metal”. In
Fanon's case the will to contest rather than to abjure humanism is rooted in
fidelity to the two ethical axioms on which his project is founded. The first
is the necessity to recognise “the open door of every consciousness”.. The second, which follows from a full apprehension of
the first, is that we all have the right to “come into a world that [is] ours
and to help to build it together.”
The character of the bright metallic
strength that Mbembe discerns in Fanon's thought is drawn from the experience
of being a subject amongst subjects “on the common paths of real life”. Fanon is clear that it is forged in action and
requires ongoing ethical engagement with the self as well as others. This makes
it entirely different to the ruthless will to power that can come with modes of
politics that speak in the name of justice from within the blinding pain, fear
and rage of a collective wound, fantasies of a privileged access to ethical
enlightenment or strategic capacity, the politics of the synecdoche in
which a part believes that it stands in for the whole, or a sense that states
or economies are inhuman forces to which progress requires accommodation rather
than contestation.
For Fanon the capacity for reason is central to human
being. This is, of course, an ancient idea. For Aristotle the human, as
political animal, is separated from other animals by the capacity for speech,
which is not the same as voice, as it extends beyond the ability to communicate
pleasure and pain to enable discussions on the question of justice. Aristotle
concludes that “It is the sharing of a common view in these matters that makes
a household and a state.” But when the agora is not
open to all, when the right to speech is not extended to all and the mere
appearance of certain people in the agora is considered to be illicit a
dominant view will often be mistaken for a common view. In many cases its claim
to constitute a common view will be rooted, along with other modes of
containment that divide those presented as having a capacity for speech from
those assumed to have a mere capacity for voice, in exclusionary spatial
practices – the woman, the worker, the raced other and the foreigner all in
their place – and often kept there by forms of policing, some discursive and
some simply violent.
Our prospects for a democratic future, for democracy
as a democratising process, for 'an association of free human beings who educate one another' is
receding in the face of a state willing, amongst other things, to use murder as
a form of social containment. But the democratic prospects that remain will not
be realised if we do not find a way to look beyond
elections and civil society to affirm that there is thought amidst waste and to
open the agora to all.
Grahamstown, October 2013
This
essay draws, in part, from a seminar presented at WISER, at WITS, in May last
year; a public lecture given at the University of Illinois in March this year
and recent papers published in City, The Journal of Asian & African
Studies, South Atlantic Quarterly and Thesis Eleven as well as two forthcoming
pieces. George Caffentzis pointed to an important omission in the first draft.